MATHEMATICAL LOGIC IN LATIN AMERICA A.I. Arruda, R. Chuaqui, N.C.A. da Costa (eds.) © North-Holland Publishing Company, 1980
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS FOR ARBITRARY QUANTIFIERS Xav.leJL Ca..leedo
ABSTRACT.
Loow(K) is the logic obtained by adding a
KX1 ••• Xk (¢I(X 1)'" ¢k (X k ) ) to the logical operations of L oow' The corresponding
lindstrom's quantifier
finitary logic is L w w (K), and L oo w (K-i.) -i.E I is obtained by adjoining a family of quantifiers. In this paper, we give back-and-forth systems characterizing elementary equivalence in those logics and their fragments of bounded quantifier rank. This general izes work of Fra'l s se and Ehrenfeucht for L w w ' Karp for L oow ' Brown, Lipner, and Vinner for cardinal quantifiers, Badger for Magidor-Mal itz quantifiers, and others. Our systems apply to higher order quantifiers also.
INTRODUCTION. Ehrenfeucht 1961 and Fraisse 1955 gave back-and-forth or game theoretical characterizations of elementary equivalence in first order logic, L ww ' later generalized by Karp 1965 to infinitary logic,
L=w' These characterizations were used
to obtain results about definability of ordinals and preservatio~ of elementary equivalence by operations on structures. Lindstrlim 1969 used Fraisse-Ehrenfeucht games to characterize L ww ' Back-and-forth systems for logics with cardinal quan-
tifiers are due to Vinner 1972 and others. Badger 1977 gives systems for 1ogi cs with Magidor-Malitz quantifiers (Magidor and Malitz 1977), and shows the fail ure of interpolation and preservation of elementary equivalence by products in these logics. Krawczyk and Krynicki 1976 give systems for certain monotonic quantifiers, without any appl ication. Makowsky 1977 a has similar systems and he studies monotonic quantifiers in detail. Back-and-forth systems for Stationary Logic, L{aa) (Barwise, Kaufmann and Makkai 1977), were given independently by Kaufmann 1978, Makowsky 1977 b and the author (Caicedo 1977 b). In our doctoral dissertation, we presented back-and-forth systems characterizing elementary equivalence in logics obtained by adding to first order logic
quantifiers of the form Q; ¢ (x), this means binding one or several variables in and a single formula, and gave various applications, particularly to L w w (Q1 ) L(aa). In this paper, we introduce back-and-forth systems appropriate for quantifiers binding several formulas: Qx·1· .. ~n(¢1(x·1)' ... , ¢n(Xn)) 83
XAVIER CAICEDO
84
Although the methods may be applied successfully to second and higher order quantifiers, as they were applied to L(aa) in Caicedo 1978, the corresponding results will be published elsewhere. We assume as known the notions of an abstract logic, as well as the extension relation between logics, and the notion of a generalized quantifier (lindstrom 1966, Barwise 1974, Makowski, Shelah, and Stavi 1976). Ol,;;&- , ... denote classical structures, and A, B, .•. denote their universes. In Section 1, we introduce quantifier symbols and their interpretations. Instead of considering quantifiers in the sense of Lindstrom 1966 and Mostowski 1957 only, we deal with the more general case of so called "weak models" where the quantifier interpretation forms part of the structure. Lindstrom-Mostowski quantifiers are recovered as families of weak models where the interpretations of the quantifiers are determined, up to isomorphism, by the domain of the structure. In Sections 2 and 3, we define the back-and-forth systems and prove the characterization of elementary equivalence. In Section 4, we consider monadic quantifierS, those where the quantifier binds a single variable in each formula, and extend a result of Friedman 1973 about the failure of Beth's definability theorem in cardinality logics to logics with these quantifiers. Also we show that any extension of Lww(QO) by monadic quantifiers satisfying interpolation must satisfy the downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorem. In Sections 5 and 6, we give a simpler version of back-and-forth for cOn~~ quantifiers, which becomes PC definable. The main applications deal with (infinitary) extensions by monadic quantifiers of L,,)w(Ql)' logic with the quantifie r "there are uncountably many". These include an analogue of Lindstrom's theorem for L ww(Q1)' a relative interpolation theorem in L ww(Q1) with respect to such extensions, and the existence of models satisfying few types in those extensions. Makowsky and Stavi discovered independently the relative interpolation theorem in L ww(Ql) and L(aa), with respect to their infinitary extensions. Finally, in Section 7 we show that elementary equivalence is preserved by cartesian products in a natural extension of logic with Magidor-Malitz quantifiers.
§1 GENERALIZED QUANTIFIERS. A qua~n~~ ~ymbot is a symbol Q together with a sequence of positive integers (111"'" l1 il > caned the type of the quantifier symbol. Given asetof relation, function and constant symbols, the language Lww(Qj) jEJ is obtained by addi ng to the usua1 forma ti on rul es of Lcos» for atomi c formul as, "l, A, and 3, the new rule: If Q. is a quantifier symbol of type (111' . . . , ttk), ¢1""'¢il are j ~ ~ formulas, and Xl' ••• , x k are lists of ttl' ..• , 11 k variables, respectively, then Q. j xl"'" X. k( ¢ 1"'" ¢ k) is a formula. It is understood that only those free variables of ¢ ~ which appear in the 1ist are bound by the quantifi er.
x~
type
If Ol
is a structure in the ordinary sense and Q. is a quantifier symbol of 11 > , thenan~n;(;eltplte;ta..t[ol1nOJt Q ~11 a is a family k
(111"'"
BACK-
Q~
9
"i nR (A ) x .•• x 9(A ).
Qj
where
AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
85
An L ww(Q.j)jE]-.6t!u.Lc.tuJLe has the form (Ol;Qj)jE]
is an interpretation of
a.
Q. j in
The semantics of Lww(Q.j)jE] is
defined in the usual way, except for the additional clause: (Ol; Qj)jE] 1=
Q. j
x1,···, xn (
(1I'x 1
xk.
q,k)E
11'
q,1 , ...
,11'
xq, = {Ct I (Ol ;
Qj) j E]
Loow(Q.j)jE]
The language
"s : 1=
if and only if
where
I
a. )}.
and its semantics are defined similarly, allowing
infinitary conjunctions. The quantifier rank of a formula of this language is the ordinal defined inductively by: qr (q, )
=
0,
if
q,
is a tomi c
qr (--, q,) = qr (q,) qr (1\ e) = sup {qr ( q, ) 1 q, E
(J }
qr (3 x
(0.. j xl"'"
where Let
~
then
x11. (4)1'''''
l' ... , nk ) is the type of 0.. j'
(n
be an ordinal, or the symbol
L:
w (Q.j')
'E] j
q, 11.)) = m1 x qr (q, -i ) + max n , , -i -<-
considered greater than all the ordinals,
~
consists of the formulas of rank less than ~. Two quantifier '"
~ -elementarily equivalent, ta , Qj)jE] == (~; tr.j)jE]' i f they satisfy the same sentences of this language. The proof of the following lemmas is similar to that of Lemma 3.2.1 in Caicedo 1978. structures are
LEMMA 1.1
I6.the numbetr. 06 tr.e1.a.ti.on, 6u.nc.:Uon,
COIl.6.tant,
a.nd
Qu.a.n~-iMetr.
.6yrnboL6 M MnUe, ~hen L~w(Q.j) jE] -l.6 eQu.-lvalent to Lww(Q.j) jE]" Motr.eovetr., 6otr. each MnUe nand k thetr.e -l.6 a MnUe numbetr. 06 non-eQu.-lva.fen.t 6O!tmula.6 06 Qu.a.nU6.(etr. tr.a.nk equ.a.f.to n w.Uh ~ mO!.>~ R va.tr.-<:a.bfu.
LEMMA 1.2 L ~w (Q.j)j E ]
G-iven
ta.,
Qj)jE]' thetr.e-l.6 ~mO.6t
a.6et 06
6otr.mu.fa.6 06
wh-lch Me 1l0n-eQu.-lva.fent -in th-l.6 .6.ttr.uc.tu.tr.e.
A
A Und.6.ttr.om-Mo.6tow.6U Qu.a.nU6.(etr. 06 type (n l' ... , n k) is a function 0.. which A n m n assigns to each set A a quantifier interpretation Q.(A)c fI(A 1) x .•. x or (A r), with the proper-ty that if 6: A -+ B is a biject1on, then for all (S 1'"'' Sk)'
(Sl,,,,,Sk)EQ.(A)
iff
(6'(Sl), ... ,6'(Sk))EQ.(B).
Itisreadily
seen that
this corresponds to the definition of a quantifier as a c'ass K of structures of the same type, closed under isomorphism (Lindstrom 1966),. by defining
Q(A) = {(Sl"'"
Sk)
I
(A, Sl"'"
A Lindstrom-Mostowski family of quantifiers {Qj L+
of
Sk)
E
I jE]}
K}. defines
an
extension
L0 JW in the sense of Lindstrom 1969 and Barwise 1974 by taking the sen-
86
XAVIER CAICEDO
tences of
Loow(Q.j )jEJ
as the .6tjn.ta.x., and defining for an ordinary structure
if.
a When the quantifier
(a; Qj(A))jEJ 1= 1>.
iff
interpreting the symbol
Qj
the language writing
1>
for
Loow(lJ../)jEJ
L+.
Qj is understood, we will abuse
The existential quantifier is the Lindstrom-Mostowski quantifier
3(A)
defined by the function well know.
=
{S
C
-
A
Is*-
0}.
of type (1 )
The following quantifiers are
CMd£na.t qua.ntiMe.M, type (1), for each ordinal a: Q.a(A) = {S:=.Allsl ;;;. wa}. for each ordinal a and finite 11., the quantifier of Q.~ (A) = {S :=.An 13 I ~A such that In ~S and III;;;. w } . a
Mag~do4-Maiitz qua.nti6~e.M,
type
(11.):
Chang qua.ntiMeJt, type (1) : Q.(A) = {S ~ A I HaJz.t.i.g qua.ntiMeJt, type (1,1): H(A) HenlUn qua.ntiMeJt, type (4) : Hen(A)
lsi = IA\}. {(S, T) I S ~A, T ~A, lsi = ITI}. 4 {S ~ A I 3 6, 9 : A -+ A such that 6Xg ~S}
Note that the logics obtained from these quantifiers do not incl ude those where the meaning of quantifier is not determined by the domain of the structure, like Sgro's topological logic (Sgro 1977). However, if we consider only logics for classical structures with a finite number of relations, functions, and constants, then any logic is a sublogic of some Lww(Q.j)jEJ' Even more, if the logic L is closed under substitution of relation symbols for formulas then L is equivalent to some Lww (Q.j ) j E ] '
§
2 BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS,
Through this section (a, q) and (~, 4) will be quantifier structure where q 4 are interpretations for a quantifier symbol of type (11. " " , n ). A and k 1 B are assumed to be disjoint. Sequences in An u s'' (11. E w) wi 11 be denoted
and
a,
a, a', a', T, T ' , h, h'; the value of catenation is denoted by juxtaposition.
11.
will be clear from the context.
Con-
DEFINITION 2.1.- A baek-and-6olLth be;tween (a; q) and (~; 4) consists of a linearly ordered set p = (P, <), called the set ofpa4amete4.6, and a family
{E~
I pEP}
of equivalence relations in
An U
s"
for each
nEw, subject
properties (i) to (iv) below. Before stating the properties, we introduce some convenient notation. will denote
(a, a')
E
E~; the value of
11.
will be clear from the context.
a
to p
a' For
~
each k, It and a E A k , we can restrict the equivalence relation Ek+n to elements of A n in the following way: R, iff a R, a ii' E An). For
a a'
k = 0 and a = 0 we get lence relation.
EP 11.
restrict~d
to
a
An,
a' (a,
Obviously,
R,a
is an equiva-
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS ..., p
..
ra Ta = Ix
n
A Ia
E
... P
X
'V
a
is the corresponding equivalence class of in ing the language, [X]~ = u {[al~ I EX}.
a
87
.. a a}
An.
If X ~ An we write, abus-
B.
Analogous notation and observations are valid with respect to sequences in PROPERTI ES.
0
(z)
p 'V
0
(Extension property). Let p', then for all sequences a in (-U:)
pf., =
exist functions
n': .{.
n.
A .{.
n.
-+
= max A and
.6
B .{., 1 <;,i
{n T
1 , · •• , n I<} and p < PI <; in B such that a R, T
... < there
< 1<, such that:
• p ~ n· (A) a a 'V T (i(a) for all a E A .{., 1 « t. < L n,i p p (B) If X,[~A ,l<,i
implies
([ n'l (X 1) If , ... , [nrl< (X I<)]~)E ".
A and B. p (,iv) (Isomorphism property). If (a ... , an) 'V (b ... , b then the assign1, 1, n) ment a,it-'>b,i isapartial isomorphism from 01- to&. As (-U:), interchanging the roles of
(.i..u:)
DEFINITION 2.2.(01-; Cij)jEJ
each
jEJ.
(p, {E~I pEP, nEW})
isa
:to ($-;Jr.j}jEJ ifitisonefrom (OI-;Cij) The existence of such a relation is denoted by
baek-and-6oJvth
to
(:6-';"j)
(a;Cij)jEJ~
61tOm
for
()&..;\)jEJ
REMAR K. We assume that any back-and-forth sa ti sfi es the extensi on property for the existential quantifier. It is enough to postulate in (,i,i) , for each p' p a 'V T and p < p' the existence of a function 6: A-+B such that o a. 'V T 6 (a). Property (B) holds automatically. DEFINITION 2.3.- {E I nE w} is a bael<-a.nd-noJt:th wUhou:t pMamUeJt1> 61tOm n ioi, Cij)jEJ to ($-; "j )jE] if En is an equivalence relation in An U Bn for each n , and properties (,i) to (,iv) of Def. 2.1 hold, dropping the parameter conditions.
§
Such relation is denoted by (or; Cij) jE]
'V
(~; "j) jE]
.
3 CHARACTERIZATION OF ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE.
Let or and!tJ., be classical structures. C = {Cij I jE J} and D = {\ I jE J} are interpretations in 01- and~, respectively, of the quantifier symbols
XAVIER CAICEDO
88
{Q.[ jE]}. j
THEOREM 3.1. -
(ot; C) ~ (~; D) then (ot; C)
I6
Suppose (ot;C) ~ (~; D). Bn define:
E
a
{J
(ot, a; C)
iff
"val
iff
(:e-,1';D)
(ot, a; C)
iff
and a, a'EA Yl
For every {J
PROOF.
r ,1"
[o ,« ) "V (%--; D).
{J + 1
(Ol, a' , C ).
-
{J+l
==
(~,1";D).
{J+l
(:e-,
-
T
;
We show that this gives a back-and-forth with parameters (e ,«},
(J "V
D) • It is clear
that
is an equivalence relation and properties (i) and (iv) of Def. 2.1 hold. Since Given a E An, dE Ak, {J
eLi) and (-UA:) are symmetric, it is enough to show (u).
let
t~ a
= {
and
(Ol,a;C) 1=
a
By Lemma 1.2, the conjunction /\ t may be considered a formula of Since the logic is closed under negations:
Loow (2..; )j E f (1)
Now we are ready to check the extens i on property. symbo 1 of type
) and
Yl
(Yll"'"
.
k
and {J < {J 1 < ... < {J -6 = {J'. (Ol, a; C)
1=
::I
-6
= m~x .{.
.{.
{J + n or;;;{J + -6 or;;;{J'. i
Since a "V
T
(Ol,a;C)
and so /\ t.( a
(g"
b),
rank or;;; {J
T; D)
and define
we have
a
{J' + 1
x..{. /\;t.a ( x.). .{.
::I
1=
6. (a)
.{. (Ol, a,
£;
=
b.
be a 1J'
Suppose that a"V
T ,
qua n t i f i e r with
T E
BYl
E A .{., (oz, a; C) 1= /\ t a. ( d ), and so last formula has qr = qr (/\ t.) + Yl • a .{. then:
For each
(x .{..).{J' This a
X. /\ t .
Yl.. .{. Yl.
Qf'
Let
Since
{J + 1 C) -
(~,T;D)
Choose t:»
a
bE
(2)
n.
B.{.
such that (~,T ; C) 1=
is a complete set of
formulas {J
(i6--, T, 6..{. (d); D ) and so a a"V
T
of
6 (d),
the first condition of the extension property.
n.
Now let x..{. c- A.{., i •V
aEX.
.{.
/\
c ; (Xl. a
=
1, ... , k.
By (1) : [ X .]{J
.{. a
For each i
let T;(x) ~
be the formula
89
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS Similarly, in ~ :
13
[ 6'.-L (X.) I = {x E B -L r
n.
-L
I
(lr,
T ;
D)
T;
F
~
(x )} .
Moreover, the formul a ~ xl , ..• , xk (T 1 ( xl) , .•• , Tk ( xfz )) has qr = 13 + .6 .;; 13 I Therefore, by (2) and the definition of quantifier, ([X J13 , ••• , [XI..]13 ) E q. 1 a '< a j implies succesively:
(01., a; C)
F
QjX 1 " " , xfz(T1(x1),
,TIt(XIt)) ,
(s-,
1=
Qj ~1 , .•• , Xfz (T1( xl)'
, Tit (x It)) ,
T; D)
([6'1
(x1)]~
, .•. , [6'fz
•
(Xfz)l~) E\. •
REMARK 3.2.It is clear from thedemonstration of the last theorem that the functions 61 " " , 6 in the extension property may be chosen homogeneously, k so they work for all quantifiers of type (n l' ... , n ) . Even more, it is possifz ble to choose for each p', a, and T, in advance, a family {6 n: An .... B n In E w} which works for all quantifiers.
16
PROOF.
(Ol; C)
Assume
a'VT
'V
(ex ,<)
(JIy; D).
'V
ex (01.; C) == (;G-; D).
(~; D) then
We prove by induction
qr(¢).;; 13 < ex, then for all
¢ ( !j) , that if
plexity of the formula
13
(ex ,<)
(al; C)
THEOREM 3.3.-
on the
com-
a
T
and
,
implies: (al; C)
(~;D) 1= ¢(r).
iff
¢(a)
1=
The result follows from property (~) taking follows from the isomorphism property (~v). let ¢ = Qj xl"'" suppose that (1) holds for ¢1'"'' ¢k' let p + .6 .;; 13. Define for each ~: conjunctions is trivial.
X.
-L
= {a
Y. = {b -L
< P + 1 < '"
Since
p
tions
6.: A -L
n.
-L ....
n.
ft. E A -L
E
n.
B
-L
(1)
a = T = 0. For atomic formulas, The inductive step for negations
xfz
p
(¢1"'"
= m~x
¢fz)
qr(¢~),
= m1x
qr';; 13 n~,
and then
-L
(01., a; C)
1= ¢. (Ci ) }
(:6-,
1= ¢. (Ii)}
T; D)
be of .6
(1) and
-L
-L
< p +.6 .;; 13 , then by the extension properties there are func-
B -L,
n.
g.: B -L
n.
-L ....
• p
A
•
aa'Vr6·(a)
• P
-L
•
Tb'Vag~(b)
If ( [Xl] ~ , ... , [X k J ~ ) E qj
then
-L
such that for all for all
n. Ci E A -L n.
bE
B
•
-L •
(I) (I I)
([6~(X1)]~,... ,[6~~Yk)]~)EItj" (III)
90
XAVIER CAICEDO
Xl. = [XJ.]~'
CLAIM 1.
Yl. = [Yl.j~.
If aal~aa· where (Ol,u;C) 1= tP.(a),then(~, T;D)l=tP.(fi.(a)) .{. .{. .{. because of (I), the fact that qr (tP) '" p , and the induction hypothesis. By transitivity: a at ~T fi. (a), and so we have again ia , a, C) = tP. (at). This shows .{. .{. [X..{. jPa eX.. The other direction is trivial, and the case of Y..(. is similar . - .{.
6'..{.
CLAIM 2.
(X.) c Y., .{. -.{.
g'. (Y.) -c x.{..• .{..{.
This follows from (I), (II), and the induction hypothesis for [fii (X;.l]~ = Yl.'
CLAIM 3.
tPl.'
[gi (YJ.)]~ = Xl.'
The inclusion from left to right follows from Claims 1 and 2. then
.P • P • T b'Vag.(b)'VTfi.g.(b) and so .{. .{. .{.
.P. b'Vfi.g.(b). T .{. .{.
Suppose
6E
Yl.
•
Butg.(b)Egt.(Y.)cX . .{..{. .{. .{.
and we have bE[fi'.(X.)]p . .{. .{. T By (III), (IV), and Claims 1 and 2, we have that (Ol, U; C) 1= Q.j ;1""';11. (tPl""'tPlz) iff (Xl'oo.,XIz)Eq. iff (Y1,oo.,YIz)E!Z.. iff ($-,T;D) 1= • •
Q.j "1"'"
j
"Iz (tP 1' ... , tP Iz ).
COROLLARY 3.4.00
(b)
(Ol; C ) =:
(:& ;
j
•
a ~ ,e) (Ol;C) =: ($--; D) J.fifi (Ol; C) 'V (~; D). (a ,e) l.fifi (01-; C) 'V (~; D ) fiM aU. MeUnaL6 a.
(a) D)
COROLLARY 3.5.Ifi the. fiamiliu C, D and the. !>.iJni1.aJU...ty typu ofi Oland lJ, Me. MnJ..te., the.n the. fioUowJ.ng coneUUoM Me. e.quJ.va.Ce.n.t: (or; C ) =: ( J,; D) (e.quJ.va.Ce.n.t fio!Z. MnUMy fioJunulM) , (w,e) (Ol; c) 'V (X-; D ) ,
(01- ; c)
(n ,e ) 'V
(Z-; D)
fiM
PROOF. (J.J.) => (ill) and (ill) Lemma 1.1 and Theorem 3.1. •
=>
aee
nEw.
(l.) ar.e trivial; (J.)
There are more convenient characterizations of Corollary 3.4 (b). THEOREM 3.6. (l.)
The. fioUowing Me. e.quJ.va.Ce.n.t:
(01-; C ) ~ ( ~; D ).
00_
=>
(J.J.) follows
from
elementary equivalency than
91
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
(u) (Ol; C)
~
(-Lil) (Ol; C)
'V
PROOF.
(.i)
=>
( ;g,; D) (Xr; D) (-Lil).
wheJte P 1.1> non-well. ondened, (bac.k-and-6oJtth wUhout Pa.JLamet:eM).
The same as the proof of Theorem 3.1, but
simplifying
the definition of back-and-forth to: a 'V 0' iff (Ol, a; C) ~ (Ol, 0'; D), etc. Instead of t~ one defines t .. = {4> (y) I (Ol. 0; C ) F 4> (a)}, By Lemma 1. 2, a. a. fI t .. is a sentence of L (Qj') j' E ] ' The rest of the. proof is simpler because a. oow we do not need parameter conditions. Choose any non-well ordered set P and define 0 ~ t iff a » t , Let PI> P2 > ,., be an infinite descending sequence of P , One shows, as in the proof of Theorem 3.3, by induction on the complexity of 4> (y) , that for all n: => (U).
(-Lil)
(U)
=>
(i),
o
Pn 'V
implies:
r
(Ol; C ) F 4>(a)
iff
(~; D ) F 4>(r),
To use the extension property in the inductive step for one chooses
§
4
P n + .:\
< P n +.:\ _ I < .. , < P n ' •
Qj
xl.· ... xm(4) l' ,, . , 4>m )
INTERPOLATION AND MONADIC QUANTIFIERS,
A quantifier symbol of type n(x ,This includes the cardinal quantifiers Qa: "there are at least wa eln ments", as well as Chang's and Hartig's quantifier, but notthe Magidor - Malitz quantifiers. Throughout this section L M will denote the logic L oow (Q.). E ] , j j where Qj runs through all the possible Lindstrom-Mostowski monadic quantifiers.
»·
LEMMA 4. I . -
a =L
oow
16 Ol and :t; Me .:\:tJtuc..tu!l.u 06 poweJt at
(Q):tr impUu
I
a
=L;,t-
M
mO.6:t
wI' then
•
PROOF. Let 2n = {o I 0 : n ... 2 }, for seA 1et sa = Sand sl = A - S • For each nEw and F: 2n ... {K 'K cardinal, K" wI} define the quantifier:
~(A)={(SI,.. "S)',;/OE2nl n
l~~)I=F(O)}, Since a monadic structure n L« n ,(. (A, SI".'. Sn) is completely determined by the above set of cardinals, there corresponds to it a unique F such that (Tl'".,T n) E Q F (8) i.ff (8, T1,.", Tn) "" (A, SI" ." S). Let 3!K x 4>(x) mean that the truth set of, .4>(x) has exaclty K n elements (K';; wI)' Clearly, for structures of power at most wI' Ol=L (Q);6implies
a
=L
(Q
3,K)
Ir.
and so
oow l' , K definable from the former quantifiers.
oow 1 (Q),(",' because the QF' s are oow F F If ~O is 4> and 4>1 is I 4> :
a
=L
92
XAVIER CAICEDO
() () ) QF"l"'" ( '1>1"1"'1>" rt
rt
rt
=>
f\ I>E 2 rt
1 (,,)1> (i I 1 . [3.' F(I> ) x i
(en;
Q (A))F 'V (ho; QF (B))F' To conclude the proof, we show F that the given back-and-forth has the extension property with respect to each monadic quantifier, and apply Theorem 3.3.
By Therorem 3.6:
~r
Let
a
<~
~
'V T ,
I,
and let
6:
If
A -+ B be the function given
QF's
by the extension property for all the
homogeneously
(see Remark 3.2).
M=([X11~"",[Xh]~)EQ;(A),choose F
such that
MEQF(A),
thenM' =
([ 6' (Xl) J~ , ... , [6' (Xh) l~
(B, M')
and so
) E QF (B) by the extension property. Hence, (A,M) "" M' E Q.(B) by definition of Lindstrom-Mostowski quantifier . • j
The proof of the following lemma is analogous.
Qa
Let
runs over all the cardinal quantifiers.
en
L ww(Q), where
==
k
or == jJ.L M In Friedman 1973, Friedman gives a sentence '1>
LEMMA 4.2. -
L C
L = Loow(Qa)aEOr,where C
hnpUu,
of
Lw(v(Qa) (respectively,
Q is Chang's quantifier) containing a relation symbol
P, such
(a,
P) 1= ep.
that for every Ol
there is at most an interpretation
P for which
However, K = {en I (en, p) 1= ¢ for some P} is not elementary in L This is shown C' giving a pair of structures en EK,:f:.- f/- K which are elementarily equivalent in L It is observed that this is enough to show the failure of Beth's definability
C'
theorem for any logic between
Lww(Q",) (respectively
Lww(QJ) and
Lemma 4.2, we have: THEOREM 4.3.Beth (Lww(Q), LM)
Beth (Lww(Q",),L
6iLU6.
M)
6iLU6
60JLarty
a>O.
L C'
After
MAD,
For example, Beth's theorem does not hold in logic with the Hartig quantifier since it is between L ww (Q) and LW The first part of the last theorem is not true for a = 0
because
satisfying interpolation; (see Barwise 1974). ic
L
is a sublogic of w 1w hence, Beth's theorem.
L extending M
Lww(QO)
and
The same is true of l:!.(Lww(~))
The next theorem imposes a restriction in such logics. A log-
L+ has 4elat£vizat£ortO if for every monadic predicate V and sentence ¢ of L+ ¢ V such that ta , V) 1= ep V iff en,.. V 1= '1>. Here, V is
there is a sentence
an interpretation of
V and
m~ V
is the restriction of the universe and
rela-
tions of en to the set V. Almost all interesting logics have this property. An exception is logic with Chang's quantifier. The Lowenheim numbe4 of a logic L+ is the smallest cardinal of power at most
K.
K
L+ has a model it has one L+ satisfies the downward Lowenheim-Skolem
such that if a sentence of
It may not exist.
theorem if its Ulwenheim number is
co ,
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
THEOREM 4.4. -
Le;t
L+
93
be a tog.£e between
L ww and L hav-i.ng Ile.eauv-i.M L+ has Lowenheim numbeJr. «, then 601l
16
za:tion and -baU66y-i.ng -i.ntVtpota:tion.
mI .;; "1m
any -bentenee ¢ hav-i.ng -i.nMnUe modetJ> Sup {] 1= q,} = x , 16 not have Lowenheim numbeJt such. !>entenc.e haJ> modetJ> 06 MbWuvt.Uy iMge -i..ty.
PROOF.
L+ doe!> c..etJLd,[nat-
q, with infinite models of size X, X < K
Suppose that there is
,
but not of any size between x+ and K (included). By definition of U5wenheim number, there is a sentence l/J with all its models of power greater than X. Let e be a sentence whose models are the equivalence relations. The classes K 1 (respectively K ) of models of e having as many equivalence classes as a model of 2 q, (respectively, a model of l/J) are PC classes of L+, defined by the projection of the sentences: 8 /\
"6
is a function onto V" /\ 'ifx 'r1 Y (x E Y +-+ 6(x) = 6(Y)) 1\
q, V (resp.
1/1 V).
Since these sentences do not have common model s of power 1ess or equal than", K 1 are disjoint PC classes of L+. However, they are inseparable in L+.If 2 has X has equivalence classes of power X', and (A', E ') E K has (A,E) E K 2 1 X' equivalence classes of power X', an easy back-and-forth argument shows tha t and K
(A, E) =L (A', E'), and so (A, E) =L (A', E'). C M terpolation fails in L+. • COROLLARY 4.5. -
Le;t L+ be a tog-le between
tiv-lzaUon and -baU66y-i.ng -i.nteJtpotaUan, then Sk.atem theOllem.
From this we conclude that in-
L ww (12. ) and
L hav-lng IletaM L+ -6aU6Mu the dOwnwalld Lowenheim-
0
PROOF. There is a sentence in Lww(Q.O) ' and therefore in L+, which has models of power w but not larger. By Theorem 4.4 it must have Lowenheim number w .•
§
5
COFILTER QUANTIFIERS, A SIMPLER BACK-AND-FORTH.
n Let 12. be a quantifier symbol of type (n), q ~ 9(A ) is a eoMUeJr. -lnteJr.pllUaUon 06 Q. if it satisfies Monoton-i.U.ty: SEq and S ~ s' imply S' E q, and V-f.,f,Wbu.tiv-i..ty: SuS' E q implies SEq or S' E q. Obviously, q is a
q
cofilter interpretation iff the "dual" interpretation = {S I A - S €I- q } is a filter over A. In terms of the language, (m; q) must satisfy the schemata:
\!X(¢4l/J) 4(Q.xq,4Q.xl/J),and
q
tifier is w-eompte;te if u {Sn I nE w} E q implies
QX(¢V1/I)4(Qx¢VQxl/J).
is an
w- complete filter. for some n. •
Sn E q
Acofilter
quan-
Equivalently, if
Qa is w-co'mplete if its cofinality Ql' Magidor-Mal itz quantifiers are not
The cardinal quantifiers are cofilter, is greater than
w,
as is the case of
cofilter, however the quantifier
n H
o'
where
H~ xl'"
xn ¢(x 1"'"
eto x
is equivalent to the cofilter
quantifier
means "there is an infinite set n)
1
such
XAVIER CAICEDO
94
tha~
a 1, ..•• an
for all distinct
E
r
there is a permutation
'/1
for whi ch
holds".
The back-and-forth characterization of elementary equivalence may be simp1 ified in the case of logics with cofi1ter quantifiers:
DEF I NITION 5.1. A -6.{mp!e bac.k-and-60Jt.th 6/tom (al; q) to (~, Jr.) is defined as in Def. 2.1 (respectively Def. 2.3), except parts (A) and (B) of the extension property which are changed now to:
Ci-t)
aE An
For all
bE Bn such that:
there is
• P (A+) aa'VTb.
(B+) [ajP E q a
implies
[lij~ EJr..
(M:i+) The analogue in the other direction.
In the following theorem, the subscript S(Fin) indicates that there
tot,
p1e back-and-forth from classes of each
Ek
forth where each
q)
is finite.
Ek
(:&-; Jr.) where the number of
to
Similarly,
S(w)
is a sim-
e q uiva 1 ence
indicates a simple back -and-
has at most countab1y many equivalence classes.
THEOREM 5.1. - Le:t C and D be MnUe 6amL.UeJ.> 06 c.G6ille.!L quan..ti..Me.!L btte.!Lp/te:tatiOft6 and a.Mume the numbe.!L 06 /te!atiaft6 in Mc.h -6tJr.uc.tu!Le. is MMte, then: (a)
1'1
(aL; C) == (i:-; D)
r 6 in
ad~a1'1
the quan.ti Me.M
1'1
(b)
(al; C ) ==
(e.)
t
6
(z, ;
(oz; C)
(oZ; c)
in6
~
(
.t
D)
S(w)
i66
Me
(1'1,<)
'V (JY;D). S(Fin) w - c.amp.i'.e:te.:
(aL; C)
(aL; C)
(h-, D) with
P
(1'1,<) 'V
S (w)
(
lr ; D ) •
nan we!./'. OfLde.!Led, then
:c- , D ) .
PROOF. (a) Since a back-and-forth is a simple back-and-forth, from left to right follows from Theorem 3.1 and Lemma 1.1, plus the observation that the equivE~
qr at most k. For the q and Jr. are cofilter interpretations, then properties (~+ -M:i+) imply the original extension property. Given a ~T choose for each a· E An some 6 (a) = b such that (A+) and (B+) hold. Assume as in ~ BofDef. 2.1 that XCA n and [Xjk E q• Since [Xjk =u{[ajklaEX}, and a k a the number of equivalence classes of the relation 'V must be finite, the union is alence classes of
result definable by formulas of
other direction one shows that if
of a finite number of classes. By the di stri butivity of q, [aj ~ E q fo r some dEX. By (B+), [6(a)jk EJr.. Bymonotonicityof n , [6'(X)jk EJr.. T
T
(b) and (e) are similar; the converse of (e) fails because the number of finable subsets may be too large. •
de-
95
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
§
6 APPLICATIONS TO Lw w (Q1) .
Let al;. be a structure of type T;.' then [Oz.0" •. , a n] is the structure that has the disjoint union u {A;. 1;. .;; I'd as universe and whose relations are the corresponding copies of the relations of each al;.' A relation R between tures is PC in L+ if there is a sentence in L+ such that Oln)
R(Olj"'"
iff [0l1"'"
Oln'x;.]
struc-
1= ¢.
Let t : T ~ T' be an ;'nt~pnetat£on between si~ilarity types (languages) as t denotes the restri cin Barwise 1974. If oi is aT' -structure, then a tion (projection) of al to a T-structure, via t. In the case of a himple interpretation, we write a I' T.
r
LEMMA 6.1. Let C be a Mme 6amil.y 06 Und6tnam-MOhtoW.61U. quant-iMenh such. that L w w(Q1' C) hM neiativ-izaUon.6. Let t-i: T~ T.i. be .i.ntenpltetat£On.6 wh~e T .i..6 Mme. Then the 60llowing Iteiation between htJtuctunU al, $-, a.nd p
and
u
PC
.i.n the g.i.ven log-ic:
(al I'" t
1
; Qj' C)
p
'V
s(w)
(i&- I' t 2 ; Qj' C ).
PROOF. It is a routine exercise to write down sentences stating that some P {E~ I pEP, nEw} form a simple back-and-forth from a r t j to k I' t • 2
The only second order statement in the original definition, the extension property, has become first order. Q and the quantifiers of C are needed to state the ex1 tension property. Qj is also needed to put a countable bound on the number of equivalence classes. The infinite family of relations En(p, x j , ... '''n' Y1'''' ,Y n ) expressing the E~ 's may be reduced to a single one by a suitable encoding of the finite sequences, see Caicedo 1978 for details. Relativization is needed to express the meaning of each quantifier in o; I't j and :t:-l't 2 instead of [OZ,~,P, ... ] .
•
Let B(U, V, P, <) be the sentence given by the lemma where U, V, P, and
e-
In the next lemma, a class K is PC if there exists a cou.ntable set of sentences T and an interpretation :t such that K = {Ol t t I a 1= T}. L+ satisfies LS(w if every sentence (theory) having a model has one of power at most "'1' 1) LEMMA 6.2. L+
ex:tencUng
Mntence 06
L
WW
Lww(Qj)' then
(~; Qj ) w£:th
th~e
P non-weU Md~ed.
theo~e.6 Ol: and PROOF.
Let K j and K be PC &M.6e.6 06 It countably compact log.i.c 2 (Q 1) and hav.i.ng neiativ.i.zaUo n.6• 16 they aILe .i.n.6epaJtable by It
Let
:t;
may
t.: .{.
T
aILe
a
E K j , I(;- E
In CMe
+
L
K~huch:thcLt
.6ati.6Me.6
be chosen. 06 pow~ at mO.6t "'1'
~
T.
.{.
and K..{.
= {Ol ~t...(. I oi
LS(w j )
1= T .}, with ..(.
(Ol;
Qj )
P
'V
S( "')
60n countable
T...(.C L+.
By
countable compactness, we may assume the number of symbols in T and T.i. to be fi(lite
96
XAV IER CAICEDO
(see Flum 1975). Suppose K and K 2 are inseparable in L ww(Q.1)' Since there 1 are finitely many non equivalent sentences of rank at most n- in th-is logic, there
~
exist alnE K 1,
n E K 2 such that
~Lww(Q.1) .i:-n ·
Otherwise, we could sep(n,<) arate the classes by a sentence of rank n. By Theorem 5.1 (oZn;Q.1) 'V (-6- ; Q.1) ' n al n
Sew)
In this way, each finite part of the following theory of 8(U, V,
Here,
U T = {1>U 11>
of the full set.
P,<)U{T~, T~}U{P(cn)' E
n.
Making
L+ has a model:
c n + 1
By compactness, there is a model
a
= al' r t
1
and
J,
= Xo'
rYe= ra',
;t', P , ... ]
~ .t 2 , we have the result. -
It is the The next theorem is analogous to Lindstrom's theorem for L w w' best possible result in the sense that it is possible to have proper countabl y compact extensions of L ww(Q.1) by non-monadic quantifiers satisfying LS(w for 1), example logic with the Magidor-Malitz quantifiers Q.~.
THEOREM 6.3. - Le..t L+ be. a .togic betwe.e.n ltel.a.tiviza.tioYilJ, In L+ .6a-tW 6.{.v.. compac.tYle..6.6 and then
L+
L ww (12 ) and L having M 1 LS (w 1) n0lt cowu:a.b.£.e. the.oJti.e..6,
~ L ww(Q1)' +
1> E L - L ww (12 ) , then the cl asses K 1 = Mod (1) ) , 1 K = Mod ('(jl) are inseparable in lww(Q'l)' By Lemma 5.3 and Theorem 3.6, there 2 exists OZ F (jl and i&- F I (jl such that al ~ L /tY , a contradiction. M
PROOF.
Suppose
The next theorem shows that interpolation fails strongly in Theorem 4.3 for a = 1.
THEOREM 6.4.I
n they
Le..t
(jl
have. an inte.Jtpo.tant in
and
!J;
LM.
It implies
be.6entencv..on
L the.y have. One. in M,
L w w(Ql).6uch.tha.t(jlI=!J;. L ww (0. ) , 1
PROOF. Let r be the common language of 1> and !J;; if they do not have an interpolant in L w w ( Q1 ) ' then the PC classes K = {OZ r- T I or 1= 1>} and 1 K = {tr t T \;e, F 1/1} are inseparable. By Lemma 5.3, there are structures OZ I=(jl 2 and Z, F 1/1 such that (J1.. t r ~ L :t, ~ T. Therefore, 1> and !J; do not have interpolants in
L W
•
M
L ww (12 1 ) , In T ha.6 a (uncountab.tel model., it ha..6 a (u,ncouYl.ta.b.£.e) model. .6aU~nying at mo.6.t coun.tab.£.y n0lt each nEw. many n-.typv.. in L W THEOREM 6.5. -
PROOF.
Take
Le..t
K
1
T be. a couYl.ta.b.te. the.oJty in
= K 2 = Mod(T)
in Lemma 5.3.
Theyare
obviously insepa-
97
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
rable; then we have of power at most
a-6-;'.
(a, Q1) If
wI'
t
i~wJ,
(JtJ-; Q1) with P non-well ordered, in
AIt , find
bEBIt such that
ia , a)=\
a
and f(;..
;-6;
then
(Q )(i6, b)=L (Q)(Ol, a'); see Theorem oow 1 oow 1 3.6. By Lemma 4.1, ta , =L (m, Therefore, it and satisfy the same M type in L Since the number of equivalence classes of - is countable, the same
Hence,
a)
a').
M.
is true of the number of types.
a'
•
In L w w we have that a theory with infinite models has an uncountable model satisfying at mostcountably many types OVe!L ea.eh eoun;ta.b£.e ~u.b~e.t. Thi sis no't true here as shown by the counterexample:
Q x P(x), --, Q x R(x), 1 1 If x If y(P(x) /\
p(y) /\
"<
-w
ct
UltcaJt OILdeJt" ,
x =1= Y -+ 3 z(R(z) /\ x
< z /\ z < y».
Any model satisfies uncountably many types over the interpretation of R. The last three theorems hold for any countable compact logic having relativizations and satisfying Linds.-Most. cofilter quantifiers.
LS(w
where
L w w(Q1' C ) C is a finite family of
1), In Theorems 5.5 and 5.6 one must change
LM for
L w w (Q1' C) all monadic quantifiers. However, we do not know of any concrete example. On the other hand, one can show analogues of these theorems for Stationary logic L(aa)·, see Caicedo 1977 b. So, any countable theory of L ~ct) has a model satisfying at most countablY many types in the infinitary logic L(ctct)M' L(ctct) is maximal in L(ctct)M' with respect to compactness and LS(w ) , and any pair of sentences of L(ctct) with an interpolant in the result obtained by adding to
1
L(act)M have one in
§
L(aa).
7 AN EXTENSION OF Lww(QO
PRESERVED BY PRODUCTS.
In Badger 1977, L.Badger shows that elementary equivalence of structures is not
Lww(o.o
Q8
For ea(h It define an It- variable quantifier symbol R It where R It xl' ... , x lt
98
XAVIER CAICEDO
The same quantifier is obtained if one asks the set (I, <) to be well ordered or just of type (w,<). By Ramsey's Theorem this is a cofilter quantifier. Let
Lww(R
where
runs over all permutations.
n
The extension is proper because well
is definable there by the sentence I R
2xy(y
L w w(Q.o
order
definable in
Usi ng our back - and - forth
for cofilter quantifiers we show: THEOREM 7.1.-
pIWduc.M
06
L ww (ReJtved by Mn.-Ue
~:tJw.c.:twz.e.6.
PROOF.
Let
x.-
IJl and
IX
(respectively
.."
and
I
IV
)
be
L
ww
(R
mentary equivalent. Since every sentence has finitely many relation and quantifier symbols, there is no loss of general ity in assuming that the similarity type is I m finite and restricting our considerations to C = {R , ... , R }. By Theorem 5.1: w (en; C) 'V ( it:-; c ), and the same is true for en 1 and x,. I Let S(F.tn) k. B I = (w, <, {E. I n, k. E w} ), ,t = 1,2, be the corresponding back-and-forths.
.<.,n
~
x
x'
For each pair of sequences = (xl'"'' xn), = (X'I'"'' x'n) define ((x 1 x'I) , ... , (x n x'n Define E ~ in (A x A,)1t U (B x B,)n by:
».
x+ x'~ y + y' We claim that the system forth from each
IJl x OZ'
E~ .
iff
B+ = (w,<,
to!6 x ~
I
,
xEk.I ,n y
{E~ liz,
It
and
E w})
X'Ek. 2 ,n
x + x'=
y'
is a simple
bacf<-and-
with finitely many equivalence classes for
The fact that
Ek. is an equivalence relation, and properties (,t) and (,tv) of n Definition 2.1 follow easily because they are expressed by universal Horn sentences, that are preserved by cartesian products, and we defined the new relations as the "product relations" are ordinarily defined in the cartesian product. EIz has finitley many equivalence class~ because for any the equivalence clas~ of this sequence with respect to En has the form: .. .. k .. .. ... .. 1<. .. ... k. [x+x'] = {u + U' IUE I x l and u' E l x"] l . Iz Therefore, if E~ has M classes and E~ has N classes, E has MN
x+ y
classes. IJ
=
X+
x'
pose that
It remains ton show the extension
E (A x AI)n and
k + Jt < Iz'.
T
=
Y+
proper't~
yIE(BxB,)n
(u+ -Lu. +) for ea:h R": Let
be such that
IJ~T, and sup-
By definition: ~
x
Iz' 'V
~
y
and
x'
Iz' 'V
y'
(l)
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
Let
b=
a + a'
E (Ax A' )"l.
b'
(6 1"", bJt) and
By the extension property in B and 1 b~) E B,Jt such that:
B 2'
there
exist
= (bi, ... , ..
.. tjb
k.
of.
xa
of.
'V
and
[Gi11ERJt(A)
[a' l~, From (2):
99
~
E
k
x'a'
'V
(2)
[bl~ERJt(B)
implies
(A') implies
....
tj'b'
[b'l~,
E
R
Jt
(B').
(3)
.. .. k ..... (0. a + a' ) ~ (r , b + b').
It remains to show that (4) below implies (5):
s=
t
a-
.l'lk E RJt(AxA') o
(4)
[b+ b'lk E RJt(BxB')
(5)
r
Assuming (4), we get a linear order (1, <) of type tha t for all (u 1 wI) < ... < (u Jt W Jt) ; n 1,
(x,
U
l' ...•
(x', W 1'"
.•
U
Jt)
W Jt)
k 'V
k 'V
(w,<) with
1 ~AxA'. such
('x, Gi)
(x', ci')
If J and J' are the projections of 1 in A and A' respectively. one of them, say J. must be infinite. Choose a function 9 : J ...J' such that (u,e(u))EI for )). all u. E J, and define a linear order in J by: "i < u iff (u 2 1,g(u1)J«u2,g(u2 It must have type (w,<). Moreover u < < uJt in J implies (u )) 1 l,g(u 1Jt , uJt) E [iil~. < ... < (u Jt, g(u,,!)) in 1, and so (u 1 ' Hence, [aJ~ E R (A) • k Jt and [b 1. E R (B) by (3). Let (L. <) of type (w,<) with L c B be such that tj u1 < ...
(u W) < ... < (uJtw) in 1. Hence, «u W ) ••• (uJtW)) E S and so (x',w •••• ,w) 1 1 k • k • 'V (x', a~) 'V (tj', b'I"'" b~). By the isomorphism property of back-andforth. this impl ies b\ = ••• = b~ = b'. Define the infinite set 1+ = t x {b'} c Bx B', and order it by: (u b') < (u b') iff u < u • Then 2 1 2 1
ai, ... ,
(u b')<
<
«u 1 b' )
(uJtb'))
1
CASE 2.
Both
Then we also have
(u
Jt b') implies (u 1 ... UJt)E E
[6 +6'1:.
[bl~.
and so
This shows (5).
J, J' are infinite.
[b'l~, tj
E
RJt(B'), by (3).
Let (L', <) be a linear
order
XAVIER CAICEDO
100
of type (w,<) for which ui < ... < u~ implies (ui, ... ,U~)E [b']~' Let 6: L..... L' be a one to one order preserving function and define 1+ = {(u, 6(u)) I uE L} with the order (ul' 6(u 1)) < (u 2' 6(u 2)) iff "i < u2 iff 6(u 1) < 6(u 2). If (ul' 6(u 1 ) ) < ... < (uJt' 6(u Jt)) <6(u1),···, 6(u Jt))
E [
and shows (5) again.
then
(u 1" ' " uJt)
b' I~, which proves
E
~
[b
k
Ilj
and
«ul' 6(u 1)),··· (u Jt' 6(u Jt))
E
[b+b' I~
With this we finish the proof that
(oz. Now apply Theorem 5.1.
oz. ';
x
C)
w 'V
S (F,cn)
(~x ~ '; C )
•
REFERENCES. L. Badger 1977
An EhJten6eucht game 60ft .the muU.£va.tU.a.te qu.a.ntiMeJt 06 MaU.tz and 60me a.ppl-tca..t,(OYl6, Pac. J. of Math. vol. 72, pp. 293 - 304.
J. Barwise 1974
Auom6 60Jt Ab!.l.tJta.d Model. TheOftlj, Ann. of Ma th. Logi c vol. 7, pp , 221 - 265.
J. Barwise, M. Kaufmann, and M. Makkai 1977
Stationary Logic, University of Wisconsin, preprint.
X. Caicedo 1977 a On extensions of Lw wlQ.l)' preprint. 1977b A back-and-forth characterization of elementary equivalence in Stationary Logic, preprint. 1978
Maximality and interpolation in abstract logics, Ph.D. disserta-
tion' University of Maryland.
A. Ehrenfeucht 1961
An appl-tc.a.ti.on 06 game.!.l .to .the eompR.etene.!.l6 pJtobR.em 60Jt 60Jtmal,(zed .theoJUe.!.l,
Fund. Math. vol. 49, pp. 129 - 141.
J. Flum 1975 Ffu.t oMeJt R.og,cc and i l l ex.teYl!.lioYl6, Logic Conference Kiel, Notes in Math. vol. 499, pp. 248 - 310.
Lee t .
R. Fraisse 1955 SUIt que1.qUe.!.l da.!.l!.l,cMc.a.ti.oYl!.l des Jte.e.a..t-c:OYl!.l, ba.!.lee6!.lUlt des ,(/.)omOJtpJu:.ome.!.l Jte6.tJtein.t6, Alger-Mathematiques, vol. 2, pp. 16 - 60, 273 - 295. H. Friedman 1973
Beth'!.l .theoJtem,cn ea.Jtd-tnaU.tlj R.ogie, Israel J. of Math., vol. 14, pp. 205-
21'3.
BACK-AND-FORTH SYSTEMS
101
J. Keisler
LoMe w.U:h the quanti6.i.eJr. "theJr.e emu uneoun..ta.bty ma.ny", Ann. L09iC, vol. 1, pp. 1 - 94.
1969
0
f Ma t h•
C. Karp 1965
Fi/Ute quantiMeJr. equi.va.tenc.e, The Theory of Models, Addison, Henkin and Tarski (eds.), North-Holland Pub. Co. Amsterdam, pp. 407 - 412.
M. Kaufmann 1978
Some
results in Stationary Logic, Ph. D. dissertation, University of
Wisconsin.
A. Krawczyk and M. Krynicki 1976
Ehlten6euc.h:t gamC6 6M geneJr.a.Uzed quantiMeM, Set Theory and Hierarchy Theory, Lect. Notes in Math. vol. 537, pp. 145 - 152.
P. Lindstrllm okdeJr. pkedic.a.te togic with geneJr.a.Uzed quanti6ieM, Theoria, vol. 32, pp. 186- 195.
1966
F~t
1969
On exten6ion6 06 Etementaky Logic, Theoria, vol. 35, pp. 1 - 11.
M. Magidor and J. Malitz Compact exten6ion6 06 L(Ql, Pakt I, Ann. of Math. Logic, vol. 12, pp. 217261.
1977
J.A. Makowski 1977 a Some Mode£. TheMy 60k monotone quantiMeM, Arch. Math. Logik, vol. 18, pp. 115 - 134. 1977b Elementary equivalence and definability in Stationary Logic, II Mathematisches Institut der Freien Universit~t, Berlin, preprint. 1978
Quantifying over countable sets: Positive v s , Stationary Logic.
II Mathematisches Institut der Freien Universitat, Berlin, preprint.
J.A. Makowski, S. Shelah and J. Stavi 1976
tJ.-
togiCA and geneJr.a.Uzed qua.ntiMeJr., Ann, of Math. Logic, vol. 10, pp , 155 192.
A. Mostowski 1957
On a geneJr.a.Uza.ti.on 06 quanti6ieM, Fund. Math., vol. 44, pp. 12 - 36.
J. Sgro 1977
ComptetenC6~
theok~
60k topotogic.a..e.
mod~,
Ann. of Math. Logic, vol. 11,
XAVIER CAICEDO
102 pp. 173 - 193. S. Vinner 1972
A geneJUtUzation 06 EhJLen6w.cM'
Departamento de Matematica Universidad de Los Andes Apartado Aereo 4976 Bogota D. E. Colombia