Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213 www.elsevier.com/locate/disc
Spaces with congruence Alexander Kreuzer, Kay Sörensen Technische Universität München, Zentrum Mathematik, Boltzmannstr. 3, 85747 München, Germany Received 11 October 2004; received in revised form 30 November 2005; accepted 27 November 2006 Available online 2 June 2007
Abstract In this paper we consider an exchange space with congruence (P , L, ≡) not assuming any further geometrical properties. If the dimension of the space is greater than 2, we show that for any line G of a plane E and any point x ∈ G there is a unique perpendicular line through x in E and that any line reflection is a motion. © 2007 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Congruence; Motions; Line reflections
1. Introduction It is well known that every Euclidean plane (E, L, , ≡) [2,9] is isomorphic to an affine plane AG(2, K) over an ordered and pythagorean commutative field K (cf. [2] (24.5)). Here (E, L) denotes an affine plane, (E, L, ) an ordered plane, and ≡ denotes the congruence relation on E × E. We may consider E as a quadratic separable field extension of K with the corresponding involutory field automorphism ¯ : E → E and we have (a, b) ≡ (c, d) if and only if (a − b)(a − b) = (c − d)(c − d) for any points a, b, c, d ∈ E. There is a corresponding theorem for hyperbolic planes (cf. [2]). For both proofs one first considers the group of motions, in particular the line reflections. For the definition of a motion and a line reflection the order relation is not necessary. We need only the linear structure of (E, L) and the congruence relation ≡, but for the proof that the line reflection is a motion it seems that additional assumptions on the geometry are necessary. For example Sörensen assumes in [8] that for given lines G1 , G2 , there exist distinct lines H1 , H2 through a common point z which intersect G1 , G2 . Here we give a proof for exchange planes with congruence not using this property. In a plane with congruence (E, L, ≡) two perpendicular lines may have an empty intersection. We show that if in a plane any two perpendicular lines have an empty intersection, then the relation “perpendicular” together with the “identity relation” is transitive (cf. Theorem 2.13). If there are two perpendicular lines with a non-empty intersection, one can show that for any line G and any point x ∈ G we have a perpendicular line through x. But it is open if there is a unique perpendicular line to G through x. This is true for finite or affine planes, but not known in general. In this paper we consider a space with congruence (P , L, ≡) not assuming any further geometrical properties. (For special spaces with congruence cf. [5,6].) We only assume that the space satisfies the exchange property, which for example can be easily shown for ordered spaces. In Section 3 we assume that there are two points with a midpoint. We use the property that if two points have a midpoint, E-mail addresses:
[email protected] (A. Kreuzer),
[email protected] (K. Sörensen). 0012-365X/$ - see front matter © 2007 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.disc.2006.11.034
208
A. Kreuzer, K. Sörensen / Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213
then they have a midline in every plane. If the dimension of the space is greater than 2, we show that for any line G of a plane E and any point x ∈ G there is a unique perpendicular line through x in E and that any line reflection is a motion. It follows that for any two points b, z there exists a unique point b ∈ z, b\{b} with (z, b) ≡ (z, b ) and also point reflections are motions. For the case that there exist no points with a midpoint, we conjecture that all examples in which the line reflections are motions have dimension 2. 2. Spaces with congruence Let (P , L) denote a linear space or incidence space with the point set P, the line set L and at least three points on every line, i.e., • for any two points there is exactly one line containing them and • for any line L ∈ L we have |L|3. A subspace is a subset U ⊂ P such that for all distinct points x, y ∈ U the unique line passing through x and y, denoted by x, y, is contained in U. Let U denote the set of all subspaces. For every subset X ⊂ P we define the following closure operation U. (1) : P(P ) → U; X → X by X := U ∈U X⊂U
For U ∈ U we call dim U := inf{|X| − 1 : X ⊂ U and X = U } the dimension of U. A subspace of dimension two is a plane. For a set {a, b, c, . . .} we write a, b, c, . . . instead of {a, b, c, . . .}. We introduce the concept of a space (P , L, ≡) with congruence (cf. [8]). We assume that (P , L) is a linear space which satisfies the following exchange condition. (EC) Let S ⊂ P and let x, y ∈ P with x ∈ S ∪ {y}\S. Then y ∈ S ∪ {x} Let ≡ be a congruence relation on P × P , i.e., ≡ is an equivalence relation with (a, b) ≡ (b, a), (a, a) ≡ (b, b) and (a, a) ≡ (b, c) implies b = c. We use the notation (x1 , x2 , x3 ) ≡ (y1 , y2 , y3 ) if and only if (xi , xj ) ≡ (yi , yj ) for i, j ∈ {1, 2, 3}. (P , L, ≡) is a space with congruence if the axioms (W1), (W2) and (W3) are satisfied. (W1) Let a, b, c ∈ P be distinct and collinear, and let a , b ∈ P with (a, b) ≡ (a , b ). Then there exists exactly one c ∈ a , b with (a, b, c) ≡ (a , b , c ). (W2) Let a, b, x ∈ P be non-collinear and let a , b , x ∈ P with (a, b, x) ≡ (a , b , x ). For any c ∈ a, b and c ∈ a , b with (a, b, c) ≡ (a , b , c ) it holds (x, c) ≡ (x , c ). (W3) For a, b, x ∈ P non-collinear there exists exactly one x ∈ a, b, x\{x} with (a, b, x) ≡ (a, b, x ). We call a bijective mapping : P → P a motion, if (x, y) ≡ ((x), (y)) for all x, y ∈ P . Lemma 2.1. (i) If a, b, c are collinear points and a , b , c ∈ P with (a, b, c) ≡ (a , b , c ), then a , b , c are collinear. (ii) Any motion is a collineation. Proof. (i) By (W1) the point c ∈ a , b exists with (a , b , c ) ≡ (a, b, c). If c ∈ / a , b , then by (W2) it would follow (c , c ) ≡ (c, c), hence c = c ∈ a , b . (ii) By (i), and −1 map collinear points onto collinear points. For a subspace U and points a, b ∈ U we define MU (a, b) := {x ∈ U : (a, x) ≡ (b, x)}. We call MU (a, b) a midpoint, a midline, or a midplane of a, b, respectively, if it is a point, a line, or a plane, respectively. Lemma 2.2. (i) Two distinct points a, b have at most one point m ∈ a, b with (a, m) ≡ (b, m). (ii) MU (a, b) is a subspace of U.
A. Kreuzer, K. Sörensen / Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213
209
Proof. (i) For m, m ∈ a, b we have (a, m, m ) ≡ (b, m, m ), and (W1) implies m = m . (ii) Assume a = b and let x, y ∈ MU (a, b) be distinct points, hence (a, x, y) ≡ (b, x, y). By (W1) the points a, b, x, y are not collinear. For w ∈ x, y by (W2) it follows (a, w) ≡ (b, w), i.e., w ∈ MU (a, b). Using that every plane satisfies the exchange condition, we can show the following important lemma for a space with congruence: Lemma 2.3. Let a, b, x ∈ P be non-collinear points and let x ∈ a, b, x\{x} with (a, b, x) ≡ (a, b, x ). Then for any c ∈ a, b, x it holds (x, c) ≡ (x , c) if and only if c ∈ a, b. / ME (x, x ) it follows ME (x, x ) = E. By Lemma 2.2(ii), Proof. For E := a, b, x we have a, b ∈ ME (x, x ). Since x ∈ ME (x, x ) is a subspace of E, and since E is an exchange plane and a, b ∈ ME (x, x ), it follows ME (x, x ) = a, b. For a line L ∈ L, x ∈ P \L and a, b ∈ L with a = b there exists by (W3) the unique point x ∈ L ∪ {x}\{x} with (a, b, x) ≡ (a, b, x ). By Lemma 2.3, x is independent of the choice of a, b ∈ L, hence we may denote x = L(x). We call the following mapping line reflection ∼ x if x ∈ L, : P → P ; x → L L(x) if x ∈ / L. ∼
Clearly L is an involutory bijection with z = L(z) if and only if z ∈ L. We remark that by the notations above we ∼
can write L(x) or L(x) as well. We prefer L(x). Lemma 2.4. Let L be a line of a plane E and let p := L(p) for p ∈ E. (i) If (p, q) ≡ (p , q ) for p, q ∈ E, then (p, q, x) ≡ (p , q , x ) for every x ∈ p, q. (ii) Let a, b, c, d ∈ E be points with (p, q) ≡ (p , q ) for all p, q ∈ {a, b, c, d}. Then (x, y) ≡ (x , y ) for x ∈ a, b and y ∈ c, d. Proof. (i) By (W1) there exists a point x1 ∈ p , q with (p, q, x) ≡ (p , q , x1 ). If x = x1 , then by Lemma 2.3 x ∈ L. For any point u ∈ L , (p, q, u) ≡ (p , q , u), hence by (W2) (u, x) ≡ (u, x1 ) and therefore x1 = x . (ii) By (i) we have (a, b, x) ≡ (a , b , x ) and (c, d, y) ≡ (c , d , y ). If c ∈ a, b, then (c, x) ≡ (c , x ) by (i). For c∈ / a, b, the assumptions give (a, b, c) ≡ (a , b , c ) and (W2) implies (c, x) ≡ (c , x ) . Also (d, x) ≡ (d , x ). If x ∈ c, d, then by (i), (x, y) ≡ (x , y ). If x ∈ / c, d with (c, d, x) ≡ (c , d , x ) it follows by (W2) (x, y) ≡ (x , y ). For the proof that the restriction of a line reflection to a plane is a motion, we have to consider the closure of three points. We define for a subset X ⊂ P x, y, [X]1 := X and [X]n+1 := [[X]n ] for n ∈ N. [X] := x,y∈X
Clearly [X]n ⊂ X and since
n∈N [X]n
is a linear space, X =
n∈N [X]n .
Theorem 2.5. Let L = u, v be a line and let w, z be points and w = L(w), z = L(z). If (z, w) ≡ (z , w ) and ∼
U := u, v, w, z, then L |U is a motion. Proof. With u = u and v = v , by definition (u, v, w, z) ≡ (u , v , w , z ). We prove the theorem by induction. For x, y ∈ [u, v, w, z]1 = {u, v, w, z} clearly (x, y) ≡ (x , y ). Assume this property for [u, v, w, z]n and let x, y ∈ [u, v, w, z]n+1 . Then a, b, c, d ∈ [u, v, w, z]n exist with x ∈ a, b and y ∈ c, d. By assumption a, b, c, d satisfy the conditions of Lemma 2.4(ii) and we have (x, y) ≡ (x , y ). For X = {u, v, w, z} we have U = X = n∈N [X]n and it follows (x, y) ≡ (x , y ) for any x, y ∈ U . ∼
Theorem 2.6. Let L be a line of a plane E. Then L |E is an involutory motion with z = L(z) if and only if z ∈ L.
210
A. Kreuzer, K. Sörensen / Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213 ∼
Proof. Clearly L is involutory and z = L(z) only for z ∈ L. Let u, v, w be points with L = u, v and E = u, v, w. We set z = w and Theorem 2.5 implies the assumption. Lemma 2.7. Let L be a line of a plane E and let |E be a motion of E. ∼
(i) Let a, b ∈ L be distinct points with (a) = a, (b) = b. Then |E = id|E or |E = L |E . ∼ E = L −1 |E . (ii) (L)| Proof. (i) For any z ∈ L, (a, b, z) ≡ (a, b, (z)), hence (z) = z by (W1) and Lemma 2.1. For any p ∈ E with p = (p), we have (p) = L(p) by (W3). If there exists a point p ∈ E with p = (p) = L(p), then for any q ∈ E with (q) = q, it follows (p, q) ≡ (L(p), q) and q ∈ L by Lemma 2.3. (ii) is a consequence of (i). We define for lines A, B ∈ L: ∼
A ⊥ B ⇐⇒ A(B) = B
and
A = B.
Lemma 2.8. (i) If A ⊥ B, then A, B are coplanar.
∼ ∼
(ii) For lines A, B of a plane E we have A ⊥ B if and only if A B |E is an involutory motion. (iii) If A ⊥ B, then B ⊥ A. (iv) Let A ⊥ B and let A∪B be a motion, then (A) ⊥ (B). ∼ ∼ ∼∼ Proof. (ii) follows by Lemma 2.7(ii) since A B A |E = A(B)|E . (iii) is a consequence of (ii), and (iv) follows by (ii) and Lemma 2.7(ii).
Lemma 2.9. (i) For distinct points b, b of a plane E, there exists at most one line L in E with L(b) = b . (ii) Let a, b, b be non-collinear points with (a, b) ≡ (a, b ). Then there exists exactly one line L ⊂ a, b, b through a with b = L(b). (iii) For distinct lines L, G of a plane E, L(b) = G(b) implies b = L ∩ G. Proof. (i) follows by Lemma 2.3. (ii) For G := b, b , a := G(a) and L := a, a we have L ⊥ G and since (a, b, a ) ≡ (a, b , a ) also L(b) = b . (iii) Since G = L, (i) implies b = L(b) = G(b), hence b = L ∩ G. By [8]: Theorem 2.10. Let A, B, C be lines of a plane E through a point a. Then there exists a line D ⊂ E through a with ∼ ∼ ∼
∼
A B C |E = D |E (cf. [8] (1.15)). Theorem 2.11. For a plane E and distinct points a, m, c ∈ E with (a, m) ≡ (c, m), there exists a unique line X ⊂ E with m ∈ X and X(a) = c, i.e., X = ME (a, c) (cf. [8] (1.7.2), (1.8), (4.2)). We call X the midline of a, c in E. Lemma 2.12. The following propositions are equivalent (cf. [8] (4.3)): (a) (b) (c) (d)
There are three collinear points a, b, b with (a, b) ≡ (a, b ). For any points x, y there is a point y ∈ x, y\{y} with (x, y) ≡ (x, y ). There are two perpendicular lines A, B with A ∩ B = ∅. For a line L of any plane E and x ∈ L, there exists a line G ⊂ E through x with L ⊥ G.
A. Kreuzer, K. Sörensen / Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213
211
It is an open problem for a plane with congruence, if for x ∈ L there exists only one perpendicular line G ⊥ L through x (but for spaces see Corollary 3.5(i)). Theorem 2.13. Assume that for any two perpendicular lines A, B we have A ∩ B = ∅. Then for distinct lines G, H, L of a plane E with L ⊥ G, H we have G ⊥ H . ∼
∼
Proof. Let a ∈ L. Since G |E , H |E , are motions by Theorem 2.6, (G(a), H (a)) ≡ (GH G(a), G(a)). Because L ⊥ G, H , clearly a, H (a), GH G(a) ∈ L, and by assumption and Lemma 2.12, there exits only one point x ∈ L with (x, G(a)) ≡ (H (a), G(a)), i.e., GH G(a) = H (a). ∼ ∼ ∼ ∼ ∼ Now by Lemma 2.7(ii), G H G |E = G(H )|E , and since a ∈ / H , G(H ) = H is by Lemma 2.9(i) the unique midline of a and H (a) in E. Hence G ⊥ H . 3. Three-dimensional spaces with congruence In this section let (P , L, ≡) be a linear space with congruence and dim P 3 satisfying the exchange condition. Let A ∈ L be any line. For any two points x, y ∈ P there is a three-dimensional subspace U of P with A ∪ {x, y} ⊂ U . ∼
∼
To show that A is a motion it suffices to show that the restriction of A to U is a motion. Therefore in the following we consider a three-dimensional subspace U of P and a line A ⊂ U . Remarks. We recall that if there are two points in P with a midpoint, then by Lemma 2.12 for any distinct a, m ∈ A there exists a point c ∈ A with (a, m) ≡ (c, m). Further we remark that for affine spaces (P , L) with dim P 3 one can show that perpendicular lines have a nonempty intersection. With Lemma 2.12 it follows that for affine spaces (P , L) with congruence and with dim P 3 on every line there exist points a, c with a midpoint. By [8, (2.3)] finite planes with congruence are affine planes. Further finite affine spaces with congruence have dimension 2. Therefore finite spaces with congruence are affine planes. Lemma 3.1. Let a, c ∈ U be distinct points, then dim MU (a, c) 2. If a, c have a midpoint m ∈ a, c, then MU (a, c) is a plane of U. Proof. Since a, c ∈ / MU (a, c), dim MU (a, c) 2. If m is the midpoint of a, c, then by Theorem 2.11 in every plane E of U containing a, c there exists a line L ⊂ MU (a, c), hence dim MU (a, c) = 2. Lemma 3.2. Let A, B ⊂ U be perpendicular lines, let a ∈ A\B and b ∈ B\A. If the point m = A ∩ B exists, then X := MU (a, B(a)) ∩ MU (b, A(b)) is a line with m ∈ X. Proof. The point m is the midpoint of a, B(a) and b, A(b). By Lemma 3.1, MU (b, A(b)) is a plane with A ⊂ MU (b, A(b)) and by Theorem 2.11 there is a line X ⊂ MU (b, A(b)) with m ∈ X and X(a) = B(a), hence X = MU (a, B(a)) ∩ MU (b, A(b)). Lemma 3.3. Let A, B ⊂ U be lines with A ⊥ B and for a ∈ A\B and b ∈ B\A let X := MU (a, B(a))∩MU (b, A(b)) be a line. Then: (i) For distinct points u, v ∈ X the set {a, b, u, v} is a basis of U. (ii) It holds A(b) = X(b) and B(a) = X(a). ∼
(iii) X |U is a motion. ∼ (iv) A |U is a motion if and only if A(x) = B(x) for any x ∈ X\(A ∪ B). Proof. (i) Since b ∈ / MU (b, A(b)) we have b ∈ / X and B, X ⊂ MU (a, B(a)) implies that MU (a, B(a))=B ∪ X=b, u, v is a plane. Now a ∈ / MU (a, B(a)) shows that a, b, u, v are independent and form in the exchange space U a basis of U. (ii) Because X=MU (a, B(a))∩MU (b, A(b)), MU (a, B(a))=B ∪ X and MU (b, A(b))=A ∪ X we have A(b)=X(b) and B(a) = X(a).
212
A. Kreuzer, K. Sörensen / Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213 ∼ ∼
(iii) Since A, B are motions of A ∪ B, it follows (a, b) ≡ (a, A(b)) ≡ (B(a), A(b)) ≡ (X(a), X(b)). Now for the ∼
basis {u, v, a, b} of U we have (a, b) ≡ (X(a), X(b)) and Theorem 2.5 implies that X |U is a motion.
∼
∼
(iv) If A(x) = B(x), then A = MU (x, B(x)) ∩ MU (b, X(b)) and A |U is a motion by (ii). On the other hand, if A |U is a motion, then (A(b), A(x)) ≡ (b, x) ≡ (X(b), x) = (A(b), x) ≡ (b, A(x)). Hence b, A(b) ∈ MU (x, A(x)) and this implies B = b, A(b) ⊂ MU (x, A(x)), so A(x) = B(x). Theorem 3.4. Let (P , L, ≡) be a space with congruence and dim P 3. If there are two points in P with a midpoint, then any line reflection is a motion. ∼
Proof. Let A ∈ L, x, y ∈ P , and U := A ∪ {x, y}. As mentioned before, it suffices to show that A |U is a motion. By Lemma 2.12 there are distinct points a, m, c ∈ A with (a, m) ≡ (c, m). Let B ⊂ U be a midline of a, c, i.e. B ⊥ A and A ∩ B = m (cf. Theorem 2.11). For b ∈ B\A by Lemma 3.2 the line X := MU (a, B(a))∩MU (b, A(b)) exists with m ∈ X. Now let x ∈ X\{m}. Since ∼
X ⊥ A, B, by Lemma 3.2 the line B = MU (a, X(a)) ∩ MU (x, A(x)) exists with m ∈ B . By Lemma 3.3(iii), X |U and ∼
B |U are motions. Hence for b ∈ B \{m}, by Lemma 3.3(iv), A(b ) = X(b ), i.e., A = MU (b , X(b )) ∩ MU (x, B (x)) ∼
and by Lemma 3.3(iii), A |U is a motion.
Corollary 3.5. Let A, B ∈ L be lines in the three-dimensional subspace U with A ⊥ B and m = A ∩ B. Then: (i) B is the unique line through m in A ∪ B with A ⊥ B. (ii) For a ∈ A\{m} there exists at most one point b ∈ A\{a} with (a, m) ≡ (b, m). (iii) There exists only one line X ⊂ U with X ⊥ A, B and it holds X ⊥ C for any line C ⊂ A ∪ B with m ∈ C. Proof. (i) Let a ∈ A\B, b ∈ B\A and X := MU (a, B(a)) ∩ MU (b, A(b)) (cf. 3.2). For x ∈ X\(A ∪ B), by Lemma 3.3 and Theorem 3.4, A(x) = B(x) and A ∪ B = MU (x, A(x)). Let B ⊂ MU (x, A(x)) through m with B ⊥ A, i.e., ∼
B (x) = A(x) and B ⊥ A, X. Since B is a motion, B (a) = X(a) = B(a) and B = B by Theorem 2.11. (ii) Assume b , b ∈ A\{a} with (b, m) ≡ (b , m) ≡ (a, m) and let L, L ⊂ A ∪ B be the lines through m with L(a) = b, L (a) = b (cf. Theorem 2.11). Now (i) shows L = L and b = b . (iii) Let Y ⊥ A, B. Then Y ⊂ / A ∪ B (else Y has two perpendicular lines through m in A ∪ B), hence m ∈ A ∪ Y ∩B ∪ Y =Y and for a ∈ A\B, b ∈ B\A by (ii) it follows A(b)=Y (b) and B(a)=Y (a), i.e., Y =MU (a, B(a))∩ MU (b, A(b)) = X is uniquely determined. Clearly A ∪ B = MU (x, A(x)) for any point x ∈ X\m. Therfore for any ∼
line C ⊂ A ∪ B through m we have C (X) = X, hence C ⊥ X.
Lemma 3.6. Let z, a, b ∈ U be distinct points, let a ∈ z, a\{a} and b ∈ z, b\{b} with (z, a) ≡ (z, a ) and (z, b) ≡ (z, b ), then (a, b) ≡ (a , b ). Proof. Let H := a, z and E be a plane with a, b, z ∈ E. By Lemma 2.12 there is a line G ⊂ E with z ∈ G and ∼
G ⊥ H . For p ∈ G\{z}, by Lemma 3.2 the line X = MU (a, a ) ∩ MU (p, H (p)) exists, and by Lemma 3.3(iii), X is a motion. Since a, z, b, z ⊂ E, by Corollary 3.5(iii) it follows X ⊥ b, z, a, z, and by Corollary 3.5(ii) X(a) = a and X(b) = b . Hence we have (a, b) ≡ (X(a), X(b)) = (a , b ). In the following we assume, that there are two perpendicular lines with a non-empty intersection. Then by Lemma 2.12 and Corollary 3.5 for any two points a, b there is a unique point b ∈ a, b\{b} with (a, b) ≡ (a, b ). Now we consider point reflections. For distinct points a, x ∈ P we denote with a(x) the unique point a(x) ∈ a, x\{x} with (a, x) ≡ (a, a(x)). We call the following mapping point reflection: x if x = a, a : P → P; x → a(x) if x = a. Now Lemma 3.6 implies:
A. Kreuzer, K. Sörensen / Discrete Mathematics 308 (2008) 207 – 213
213
Theorem 3.7. Every point reflection a is an involutory motion with x = a (x) if and only if x = a. 4. Addition of points In this section we assume that any two distinct points a, a have a midpoint m ∈ a, a with (a, m) ≡ (a , m). For a fixed point 0 ∈ P we denote for any point a ∈ P \{0} the unique midpoint of 0 and a by a/2. We denote 0 = 0/2. Then for the point reflection corresponding to a/2 we have a/2(0) =a
and
a/2(a) = 0.
We define for points a, b the addition + on the point set P by (cf. [1,4]). ◦ a + b := a/2 0(b) = a/2 0(b). Theorem 4.1 (Karzel [1], Konrad [3], Kreuzer [4]). Let (P , L, ≡) be a space with congruence of dim P 3 such that any two distinct points have a midpoint. Then fixing a point 0 ∈ P , an addition + can be defined on P such that (P , +) is a Bruck loop (for a definition cf. [7]) with the neutral element 0. The point −a := 0(a) is the inverse of a ∈ P . (P , +) is associative if and only if for three points a, b, c ∈ P the product a b c is a point reflection, too. References [1] [2] [3] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9]
H. Karzel, Recent developments on absolute geometries and algebraization by K-loops, Discrete Math. 208/209 (1999) 387–409. H. Karzel, K. Sörensen, D. Windelberg, Einführung in die Geometrie, UTB Vandenhoeck, Göttingen, 1973. A. Konrad, Nichteuklidische Geometrie und K-loops, Ph.D. Thesis, Technische Universität München, 1995. A. Kreuzer, Reflection loops and linear spaces with hyperbolic incidence structure, Comment Math. Univ. Carolinae 45 (2004) 303–320. H.-J. Kroll, K. Sörensen, Pseudo-Euklidische Ebenen und Euklidische Räume, J. Geom. 8 (1976) 95–115. H.-J. Kroll, K. Sörensen, Hyperbolische Räume, J. Geom. 64 (1998) 141–149. H.O. Pflugfelder, Quasigroups and Loops: Introduction, Heldermann, Berlin, 1990. K. Sörensen, Ebenen mit Kongruenz, J. Geom. 22 (1984) 15–30. K. Sörensen, Eine Bemerkung über absolute Ebenen, J. Geom. 64 (1999) 160–166.