Agriculture in recent development theory

Agriculture in recent development theory

Journal of Development Economics 22 (1986) 41-86. North-Holland AGRICULTURE IN RECENT DEVELOPMENT THEORY J. Mohan RAO* Boston University, Boston, MA ...

4MB Sizes 0 Downloads 138 Views

Journal of Development Economics 22 (1986) 41-86. North-Holland

AGRICULTURE IN RECENT DEVELOPMENT THEORY J. Mohan RAO* Boston University, Boston, MA 02215, USA Received January 1985, final version received July 1985 This paper is a critical review of recent contributions to the literature on agriculture in development theory. It considers and compares the main lines of advance made within neoclassical, neo-Marxian and structuralist approaches. Recent neo-Marxian and structuralist studies of agrarian development reveal that traditional agriculture is neither stationary nor efficient, that resource allocation cannot be separated from wealth distribution or production organization, that forms of surplus appropriation do not necessarily follow the dictates of efficiency, that the social relations of production may inhibit accumulation and determine the forms of technological change, that the state's role in primitive accumulation is more economic than explicitly coercive/political, and that political and macroeconomic constraints preclude a simple 'get the prices right' view of the intersectoral terms of trade. The thrust of these developments is to challenge both neoclassical and some orthodox Marxian formulations of agrarian development issues and add to the insights to be gleaned from a political economy of development.

1. Introduction

The past two decades have witnessed a voluminous growth in the literature about Third World agriculture. Mainstream development economists have become increasingly interested in the problems of resource-use efficiency and the role of markets in agriculture. Marxian and structuralist economists have addressed the twin issues of the modes of production with which to characterize underdeveloped agrarian economies and the mechanisms of a projected transition to capitalism. Neither of these two streams of new thinking is internally homogeneous and much insight into the development process may be gained from looking closely at the points of discord both within and between them. The sources of inspiration for these developments are hardly coterminous. Nevertheless, a common and important one is perhaps the widely felt disappointment with the performance of both income distribution and employment expansion accompanying LDC growth. This'has become im*Amit Bhaduri and Alain de Janvry, as discussants, offered incisive comments and helpful suggestions. I have also benefited from comments by Pranab Bardhan, Jere Behrman, Nancy Folbre, Neva Goodwin, Gillian Hart, David Lehmann, Alan Richards, Ajit Singh and Lance Taylor. I would like to thank all of them. 0304-3878/86/$3.50 © 1986, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. (North-Holland)

42

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

plicitly associated with the real or imagined intellectual shortcomings of the earlier, dualist orthodoxy of development economics and the policies/actions espoused by it. One focus of the critique of orthodoxy has been what may be arguably its weakest link: the structure and internal dynamics of the 'traditional' sector of which surely the major portion is agriculture. In addition, mainstream economists have been attracted to this subject by the apparently large potential for internal agricultural development highlighted by the new biochemical technologies. Some Marxians and structuralists, on the other hand, may have been pushed into this field by their belief that internal agricultural development is necessary as part of a selective program of external delinking to reduce the costs of external dependence. They have atso been spurred by the realization that the political economy and the politics of development cannot be meaningfully separated from 'the agrarian question'. This called for a partial shift of focus from capitalist industrialization to the transition in agriculture. This paper is an attempt to understand what difference these new thrusts have made to the theory and practice of development economics. It considers and compares the main lines of advance made within neoclassical, neoMarxian and structuralist approaches. Recent neo-Marxian and structuralist studies reveal that traditional agriculture is neither stationary nor efficient, that resource allocation cannot be separated from wealth distribution or production organization, that forms of surplus appropriation do not necessarily follow the dictates of efficiency, that the social relations of production may inhibit accumulation and determine the forms of technological change, that the state's role in primitive accumulation is more economic than explicitly coercive/political, and that political and macroeconomic constraints preclude a simple 'get the prices right' view of the intersectoral terms of trade. The thrust of these developments is to challenge both neoclassical and some orthodox Marxian conceptions of agrarian development issues and greatly add to the insights to be gleaned from a political economy of development. Needless to say, the subject is vast and the themes taken up in the literature are wide-ranging. The emphasis on certain themes and the exclusion of others is due in part to my own biases and also to limitations of space. The considerable amount of work done in recent years on issues such as rural demography, consumption behavior, the rural non-agricultural sector, the determinants of nutrition levels and the like are not taken up here. Even questions concerning the rationale of state action or the efficacy of collective action - questions that are closely connected to some of the issues addressed in this paper - have been ignored primarily due to lack of space. The paper also reflects my own preoccupation with the literature on South Asia. Arguably, this does not bias my general representation of orthodox

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

43

Marxian and especially neoclassical positions. These approaches are not notable for qualifying their general propositions according to the context considered - at any rate, on the agrarian question. But certain strands of neo-Marxian and especially structuralist analyses hinge heavily on the historical-regional context within which agrarian issues are posed. Therefore, the themes reviewed in this paper fail to do justice to the full range of agrarian questions analysed within the structuralist or neo-Marxian approaches. I can only hope that others will follow suit to make up this deficiency and still find the general framework and conclusions of this paper fruitful. The plan of the paper is as follows. In section 2, some aspects of the mode of production debate of the past fifteen years are highlighted starting with a cursory excursion into the classical/Marxian positions on the agrarian question. Neoclassical and Marxian/structuralist approaches to the analysis of rural labor markets and of the links among wealth inequality, enterprise forms and resource allocation are outlined and compared. The persistence and market involvement of the peasantry are examined and related to the nature of village-level constraints on economic outcomes. The section concludes with a brief exposition of emerging views about the logic and implications of agrarian structures in contemporary LDCs. Section 3 is a survey of some recent analyses of the modes in which surplus is appropriated from the producers. Starting with an exegesis of the theoretical obstacles to competitive analyses of sharecropping, this section goes on to look at neoclassical models of sharecropping that dissect the phenomenon within a framework of economy-wide full employment. A brief discussion and evaluation of models that relate sharecropping to labor market unemployment follows. The final part of this section takes a critical look at alternative models of the widely noted phenomenon of interlinked transactions, particularly in land and credit. Section 4 is in many ways a continuation of some key issues raised in section 2 but with a focus on the process of capital accumulation as it relates to the agrarian (class) structure. This section surveys some interesting new ideas about the interaction between class structure, enterprise forms and state action in the context of capital accumulation and technological change and, where relevant, compares them. Section 5 concerns itself with new analyses of the old debate over the terms of trade or the relation between 'town and country'. Besides summing up relevant evidence on issues such as intersectoral resource transfers and the long-run impact of prices on production, section 5 compares conflicting views about what the terms of trade do to agriculture and to the rest of the economy. Structuralist modelling of the macroeconomic process and political-economy analyses of the productive and distributive roles of the state are identified as being key innovative contributions in this area. The final section attempts, imperfectly and incompletely, to weave together some

44

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

of the broad implications emerging from the review of literature of the preceding sections. A case is made for the viability and relevance of a nonneoclassical position on the agrarian question.

2. Modes of production In much of Third World agriculture, considerable numbers of direct producers work with their own means of production even where ownership concentration of land is high. A varying fraction, however, must be classed simply as dependent peasants as they are partly dependent on borrowed" capital, leased-in land or wage employment. The relatively underdeveloped extent of full-time wage labor is symptomatic of the continuing numerical strength if not economic independence of these peasants and semi-peasants. Though less obviously than is the case with landless laborers, these groups are also afflicted by the problems of inadequate work opportunities and widespread poverty. It is their ubiquitous presence in the countryside that makes class-based analysis of the 'agrarian question' so complex and challenging. The debate about agrarian modes of production has been or ought to be about the ways in which technology, control over the means of production, access to the resources of the state and the enterprise forms in which production is organized influence productivity, employment and income distribution within and outside agriculture. Mthough the debate has engendered valid reasons for scepticism about its usefulness, it is best seen as a search - yet unfinished - for a suitable macroeconomics of agrarian development. It is not easy, though, to construct abstractions relevant enough for a class analysis which will at the same time be robust with respect to the bewildering complexity of agrarian production and market relations. In part due to the limited historical/empirical bases on which classical Marxian positions have been extended or modified by the recent debate, but also in part due to a penchant for simple classificatory schemes, the debates over the mode of production have been less fruitful than they might have been. The labelling disputes that have resulted, wherein complex situations are fitted into polarities such as capitalist/feudal, autonomous/dependent, stagnant/ dynamic and the like, have not hdped in developing concrete analyses of the manner in which agricultural production and exchange are organized or accumulation and structural change actually proceed. Nevertheless, a number of Marxian/structuralist positions have emerged which do reflect serious attempts to understand the emerging situation in backward agriculture. Aspects of these new positions will be briefly reviewed in this section, focusing on their static analytic content and relating them to positions that disavow class analysis.

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

45

2.1. Marx, Lenin and Chayanov It is useful to recount the classic Marxian propositions. Historical tendencies in continental Europe, but especially in England, suggested to Marx that the decline of the peasantry was inevitable, and along with that the advance of capitalist agriculture [Marx and Engels (1968)]. The advantages of scale and superior rates of capital accumulation assured the echpse of petty proprietors in agriculture as much as in industry, although rising indebtedness, loss of land and pauperization would precede complete proletarianization. Capitalist agriculture was also expected to benefit 1 differentially from the growth of capitalist industry as agricultural inputs came to be increasingly produced by industry, further exposing the peasantry to market competition. Lenin's contribution was to point out that the social differentiation of the peasantry would develop proletarians and rich peasant-capitalists quite apart from the growth of capitalism on large estates [Lenin (1964)]. The dissolution of the peasant economy in the face of commodity market development further contributed to the growth of that (home) market thus establishing a symbiotic relation between capitalist agriculture and capitalist industry. Kautsky qualified the Marx-Lenin position by pointing out why, in some regions/countries, the peasantry and small holdings may persist over protracted periods of time: technological scale economies may be weak and there may be an effective land constraint on the expansion of large-scale farms [Banaji (1976)]. While Marx and Lenin were mainly concerned with the fate of the peasantry under capitalist development, Chayanov (1966) sought a theory of the peasant economy as a distinct mode of production. The peasant enterprise sustains itself with its own (family) labor and other means of production. Isolated from a developed wage-labor market, the peasant's economic calculus is independent of wage and profit categories. The peasant's production 'capacity' and his consumption 'requirements' are liable, though, to vary over the family life-cycle. The resulting resource imbalances could be ironed out by a suitable social mechanism of, say, land redistribution among families so that peasant economic differentiation will be demographic and impermanent. Furthermore, Chayanov thought that the peasantry were capable of appropriating scale economies without losing their peasant status: peasant cooperatives could serve the purpose even as the peasant community kept differentation within bounds. 2 1Ricardo, though, had maintained earlier that the political power of agricultural rentiers held back capital accumulation in industry. 2How a market alternative to the communal mechanism could function without giving rise to market valuations of labor and what this implies for the autonomous peasant calculus has never been worked out. Similarly, if peasant communities or villages are the building blocks of the larger peasant economy, it is not evident whether or how resource inequalities among these communities are eliminated. Neither of these questions is pertinent where land is free, which is not to say that Chayanov's conception is invalid outside that context.

46

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

All of these propositions on the nature of the peasant enterprise, peasant differentiation, and the development of capitalism, have been influential in the recent debates in Asia and Latin America. The debates have two additional dimensions of complexity because (a) 'peripheral' economies have long been integrated into the capitalist mode at the 'center' through colonialism, trade and investments, and (b) surplus extraction within agriculture has until recently been based on a variety of production relations including slavery, debt bondage, tenancy, extra-economic compulsions on petty producers, and wage-labor. The first point has led many writers to argue that capitalist development in the periphery tends to be weak and externally dependent/subordinated. The second has raised the issue of the persistence if not dominance of pre-capitalist modes of surplus appropriation involving, in particular, a weak and dependent peasantry. 2.2. Neo-classical and "neo-Smithian Marxian' positions

It is perhaps instructive to first consider 'Marxian' and mainstream views which concur in rejecting the relevance of an analysis of 'modes of production', as commonly understood, in backward agriculture. Frank (1967) equates capitalist transformation in the periphery with production for longdistance trade with the center. Capitalism is the dominant mode of production and has long since established its hegemony throughout the world, so much so that 'non-capitalist' relations of production within the periphery are instrumental or functional to capitalist expansion in the center. Similarly, for Wallerstein (1974), 'wage-labor is only one of the modes in which labor is recruited and recompensed in the [capitalist] market. Slavery, coerced cashcrop production (my name for the so-called "second-feudalism"), sharecropping and tenancy are all alternative modes'. The much-labored debate about agrarian modes of production, in short, is a non-issue for these writers. The earliest of the numerous attacks on this position was that of Laclau (1971) responding to Frank's revisionist interpretation of Latin American development (or underdevelopment). His criticism was aimed at Frank's trade-centered definition and analysis of the capitalist mode of production. One 'branch' of the mode of production discussions, viz., the structuralistdependency viewpoint, grew out of this polemic, particularly in Latin America, though it had other progenitors as well. Much of neo-Marxian writing on the Third World concedes the dominance, at a world level, of the capitalist mode of' production but there is little agreement as to precisely how that effects the underdeveloped countries. Few would go along with Frank, though, in asserting that a class analysis of peripheral economies relatively isolated from external relations is impossible and irrelevant. 3 aSince much of this literature has been reviewed elsewhere the issues raised by it will not be considered here [see, for example, Goodman and Reddift (1982)].

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

47

For present purposes, it is interesting to note that the Frank-Wallerstein position is, at least in some respects, not unlike the neoclassical approach. If peripheral economies and agriculture are uniformly and universally exploited by a hegemonistic center for the former, for the latter 'traditional agriculture' [Schultz (1964)1 is everywhere subject to the dictates of perfect competition and Paretian efficiency. The neoclassical approach is distinguished above all by the assumption that wages are determined by full employment. An overriding but perhaps unconscious concern of neoclassical economists is to demonstrate that the allocation of resources in production is essentially independent of the distribution of control over the means of production. As a corollary, they would also argue that the form of the enterprise (peasant or capitalist, for example) has no independent influence on either production or on income distribution. Economic institutions are viewed primarily as rational responses to technology. In brief, the mode of production is irrelevant; the analysis of exchange relations and description of technology guarantee knowledge of all that needs to be known about the economy. The ultra-neoclassical position was, of course, first.championed by Schultz in relation to backward agriculture. Schultz's (1964) world of traditional agriculture is one where technology is stationary and (if the Malthusian ghost is not to be invoked) population also is somehow stationary. But Schultz demands more out of traditional agriculture: it is also efficient though poor. Explicit and implicit markets exist to ensure full employment of all resources and their efficient utilization. Within the traditional technology, given these assumptions, there cannot be any surplus labor. Inequality in the control over the means of production is of no consequence for resource allocation. Neither is there any economically relevant distinction between peasant and capitalist enterprises. The conception of 'poor but efficient' was designed, at least in part, to combat the growing influence of the classical/Marxian model of economic development with 'unlimited' labor supplies originated by Lewis (1954). As will be seen below, Schultz's position continues to exercise a major though somewhat modified influence among neoclassical students of backward agriculture. This position may be criticized from a number of viewpoints and only a few are noted here. The absence of a developed labor market in a peasant economy, as pointed out earlier, makes resource allocation subject to entirely different mechanisms than the ones entertained by Schultz [Chayanov (1966)]. In particular, resource ratios need not be equalized across peasant communities. Population growth in traditional agriculture is often accompanied by the search for new technology or the faster diffusion of known technology so that neither population nor technology need be stationary [Boserup (1965) and Perkins (1969)]. A feudal elite may be content to extract limited surplus fromcultivators rather than maximize it, and then it is plausible to maintain that resource ratios will not be equalized everywhere.

48

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

Schultz never explains why his limited view of individualist economic rationality should prevail in traditional agriculture. Traditional agriculture may be poor but neither stationary nor efficient. 2.3. The village economy: Rational, moral or political imperatives? At least two different avenues have been taken in the efforts to attack Schultz's reduction of economy-wide outcomes to individual rationality and action: otie which emphasizes village-level constraints on individual action, and another which argues that individuals internalize communal values with their actions displaying commitment to those values. According to Scott (1976) who studied the sources of peasant rebellion in South East Asia earlier in this century, the double threat of unpredictable nature and arbitrary and inflexible claims by outside political authority, compels peasants to be concerned almost exclusively with assuring themselves a socially acceptable subsistence level. Hence, they develop norms of reciprocity and the right to subsistence. The 'moral economy' of the peasant that these norms define cannot be understood in Schultzian terms. Ishikawa's (1975) formulation of 'peasant families and the agrarian community' is similarly rooted in the historical experience of Japan, China and other Asian countries, and again challenges Schultz's ahistorical formulations. The distinctive feature here is that he simultaneously emphasizes selfinterest and political (power) imperatives in the development and transformation of village institutions. Socially accepted subsistence for all is met neither because everyone shares a common moral framework nor as an outcome that is individually 'rational' for all. Conflicts exist particularly between the landed and the landless; their (partial) resolution reflects compromise through village institutions. The 'community' places restrictions on its constituent individuals and groups in respect of (a) employment and the assurance of subsistence, (b) gainful cooperation in production, (c) material help in emergencies and (d) unity against outsiders - particularly monopolistic merchants. Conflict is most apparent over the community principle of employment: 'the institutions related to employment are in general not determined on the basis of agreement among the parties. Compromise and coercion tend easily to enter the process of their determination' (p. 483). Hayami (1982) has maintained that the relative ease with which land-augmenting and labor-using technologies are promoted in South East Asia compared to India is due to the strength of the village community in the former - characterized by patron-client relationships, a traditional moral principle of mutual help and income-sharing - whereas caste and class divisions in India act as major hindrances. These non-neoclassical analyses have been challenged by neoclassical economists and others. For Popkin (1979), peasant economic maneuver-

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

49

ability is less restricted than Scott assumes. In opposing his 'rational peasant' against Scott's 'moral peasant', Popkin carries Schultz's project forward: peasant individual economic calculations govern private actions as well as social outcomes. He views cooperative or collective action as exclusively determined by the aggregation of individual economic interests: where profitable opportunities for trade or cooperation exist, markets or market-like institutions come into being to exploit such opportunities. Such arrangements may fail, however, without contradicting the hypothesis of peasant rationality. Thus, the lack of development of insurance and welfare schemes in Vietnamese villages is traced to the problems of free riders, moral hazard and adverse selection. Simply put, it could not be determined whether the poor were merely unfortunate or lazy and dishonest. Similarly, he argues that the rural rich acted as a cohesive group who exploited the others by virtue of their privileged access to political authority - a phenomenon consistent with rational action but not with moral economy. In endorsing Popkin's propositions against Scott's, Feeney (1983) believes that the growth of inequality, poverty and risks was due not to the growth of commercialization and markets but to the functioning of an imperfect political system in colonial regimes. Neither Feeney nor Popkin see any causal connection between production inefficiencies - whether due to market failures or public policy - and the unequal distribution of the means of production. Such inefficiencies - owing to costly risk-reduction strategies of the poor or to foregone land-expansion opportunities - arise in a situation where unequal access to the means of production exposes a large number of producers to the costs of market failures while also denying them equal access to political power. Perhaps Scott's claim for the moral economy is an extravagant one. But neither is Popkin's belief, that peasants are individually rational, sufficient for a complete understanding of how resources are allocated and income is determined in private or public spheres. 4 2.4. The labor market: Unemployment and dualism A key empirical relationship around which some of the mode of production debate and most of the debates about farm efficiency, dualism and 'surplus labor' have been structured is the widely-documented observation that farm size and labor intensity (and, to a lesser extent, land yield) are ~The above criticism applies more generally to a large number of papers that analyse the static efficiency of various kinds of 'competitive' market relations in underdeveloped agriculture. A broad class of explanations relies on information costs, moral hazard, supervision problems and wealth-dependent attitudes to risk to establish the Pareto optimality of exchanges particularly in factor markets. But the link between inefficiency and inequality does not disappear merely because the constrained outcome is Paret0-optimal.

50

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

negatively related. Amartya Sen (1966) contributed a Chayanov-type model of the peasant (family) farm in order to explain both the inverse relation and the existence ,of surplus labor. The family farm's equilibrium is characterized by equality between labor's marginal product and its subjective real cost to the family. Withdrawal of labor from such farms may leave output unaltered provided peasants are poor enough to have an invariant real labor cost in the relevant range. Further, provided such real cost is below the market wage and family farms predominate among small farms while large farms employ wage-labor, the inverse relationship is to be expected. Sen's formulation, it should be noted, assumes that family farms are restricted to self-employment and also that land is not leased out to them by labor-employing farms. Given the not inconsiderable extent of land-leasing by family farms and of their labor market participation in many parts of Asia and Latin America, Sen's model is empirically deficient. Indeed, it is precisely the empirical insignificance (or at least declining significance) of a peasantry completely isolated from the wage-labor market that has prompted many contemporary writers to talk about a dominant capitalist mode of production. An alternative to Sen's model starts with labor market unemployment and derives dualism and the inverse relation from it [Mazumdar (1965)-!. Family farms may supply part-time labor to others but not be able to find employment for all of their labor. Under these circumstances, maximizing behavior of such farms will lead to a wage gap between labor-importing and labor-exporting farms as measured by the probability of not finding wage employment. Positive wages even in the presence of unemployment in some seasons or year-round is explained in terms of institutional factors - such as the ones noted in section 2.3. The classical/Marxian roots of this alternative should be self-evident. 5 Backward agriculture not only has a developed wage-labor market but also, as under capitalism, a reserve army of unemployed constituted by landless laborers as well as peasant fami'ly workers. Purely neoclassical explanations for the existence of surplus labor and for the inverse relation have also been attempted. Beginning with Leibenstein (1957), a number of authors have argued that, at low levels of worker consumption, a positive link exists between nutrition and work effort. If wages and nutrition (consumption) are also positively related, then there exists an efficiency wage which profit-maximizing employers will offer and which can exceed the supply price of unemployed workers. The economy moves out of the efficiency wage regime only when the land-labor ratio rises above a certain minimum. Quite apart from the thorny problems created (for the advocates of such theories) in explaining how the economy deals with the unemployed, the efficiency-wage hypothesis is of dubious relevance to much 5It has been eloquently defended in the Indian case by Bagchi (1973)

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

51

of the Third World's rural labor markets. As Bliss and Stern (1978) have observed, since the human body stores nutrients, the consumption--effort relationship may be virtually non-existent over short periods and, hence, irrelevant to the normal operation of rural labor markets with short-term labor contracts predominating. The neoclassical route to explaining the inverse relation is to posit various sorts of search costs and other similar frictions in the functioning of rural labor markets. Rosenzweig (1978), for instance, while maintaining that Indian rural labor markets are characterized by zero involuntary unemployment, introduces search and transportation costs associated with working for others. This gives rise to the expectation of an inverse relation between farmsize and yield, tt is a different matter, however, to reconcile such models with the infrequently denied fact of significant levels of unemployment - even though standard definitions fail to measure the incidence of discouraged, particularly female, workers. In their recent survey of some of the literature on labor markets in backward agriculture, Binswanger and Rosenzweig (1984) have made rather enthusiastic claims in support of the neoclassical approach. They find in the seasonal variations of money (real?) wage rates and in the scattered evidence on long-run movements in real wages sufficient cause to argue that reality is 'inconsistent with institutional views' (p. 31) and that it is 'largely consistent with supply and demand interpretations' (p. 30). Such a conclusion reflects a serious misunderstanding of the institutionalist position as well as an elastic empirical interpretation of the 'supply and demand' argument. The institutionalist argument is not that real wages are constant but that they are a given; neither is real wage responsiveness to changing economic conditions necessarily inconsistent with that argument. In a long-run dynamic context, the conventional wage that Marxians posit may be bargained over not as a rate but as a share [Marglin (1984)]. Besides, such wage responsiveness to 'supply and demand' conditions is by no means sufficient to favor the neoclassical position. The latter is defined rather by the absence of involuntary unemployment - an issue over which the cited 'evidence' sheds no light. These authors then go on to claim that up-to-date empirical studies (published in the volume edited by them) 'call into question the basic assumptions of the surplus labor models, suggesting that reductions in labor supplied will significantly increase agricultural wages and that the variability in wage rates over time and across space is explained to a considerable degree by variations in demand, for and supply of labor' (p. 38). One of these studies, it turns out, is an econometric study of farm labor demand and merely speculates that labor supply changes will have large wage impacts owing to a low measured elasticity of labor demand [Evenson and Binswanger (1984)]. Another [Bardhan (1984a)] explicitly contradicts the editors' conclusion: 'A competitive wage theory, for example, is not necessari-

52

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

ly confirmed by the evidence presented here in favor of a demand-supply framework ... the wage rate, even though it is sensitive to demand pressures, does not adjust sufficiently to fully clear the labor market' (p. 258). The rates of unemployment were found to be on average 11 percent (20 percent) in the busy seasons and 23 percent (43 percent) in the slack seasons for male (female) laborers. That rural land and credit markets are also characterized by significant inflexibilities was first pointed out by K.N. Raj in two remarkable studies carried out in the late sixties with Indian data [Raj (1970, 1979)]. Although there was a significant amount of land-leasing, he found little difference between the size distributions of ownership and operating units; similarly, access to credit was closely linked to ownership/control of land. Following Raj, Abhijit Sen (1981) has argued more generally that because land and credit markets remain constrained by a variety of factors, there is a connectedness between the ownership distribution of assets (land. total wealth) and their distribution in operational use. Together with the inverse relation and unemployment, this makes a strong case for the notion that the unequal distribution of ownership/control over the means of production is a major determinant of resource use in agriculture. Unemployment and dualism (or its generalization which Sen calls connectedness) appear to be the most important stylized facts about backward agriculture. It is the basic assumptions of the neoclassical approach that are thus called into question. As will be argued in section 3, recent neoclassical analyses of market relations, although displaying greater awareness of market imperfections than Schultz or his followers had, fail to come to grips with these observations.

2.5. Emergent positions While dualism and unemployment are widely accepted premises among Marxians/structuralists, there is not much agreement among them about what factors perpetuate these phenomena or about their consequences. In the rest of this section, some emerging viewpoints are briefly reviewed primarily to give a flavor of the sorts of theoretical differences that remain unresolved and that are likely to remain influential in empirical investigations.

2.5.1. Functional dualism A recent attempt to grasp agrarian structur.e and the modes of production it comprises within an overall model of development is that of De Janvry (1981). For present purposes, the significant element in his approach is that he sees a 'functional dualism' between capitalist agriculture and the peasantry in the context of a labor surplus. Left to their own devices, the peasantry would differentiate; capitalist development would rapidly proletarianize them,

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

53

and this indeed is the long-run tendency. However, the transitional survival of a semi-proletarian peasantry is functional to capitalism because part of the socially acceptable subsistence of wage workers is secured from family farms so that wage costs for capitalist employers are lowered. A related mechanism is a 'cheap food' policy including cheap imports and government-controlled prices for peasant-produced commodities which also has the effect of cheapening wage-labor. Functional dualism makes possible a high rate of surplus extraction because (i) it weakens labor's economic position by producing large-scale unemployment and misery, and (ii) the semi-proletarian peasantry with their petty peasant ideology act as a buffer for the capitalist class. De Janvry therefore opposes the view of Brenner (1977) that agricultural backwardness and poverty are a consequence of low productivity and low investable surpluses. He also rejects the position of Vergopoulos (1978) that it is the peasants' lack of a profit or accumulation motive that makes them functional to capitalism. 2.5.2. Peasant rationality and links to the capitalist mode Lehman (1982) seeks to explain peasant survival primarily in terms of the internal logic of the peasant enterprise which is externally involved in the capitalist market-place. He finds social differentiation in Lenin's sense to be a pervasive aspect of Latin American and South Asian peasantries and therefore rejects the classic Chayanov position regarding peasant differentiation. Yet the persistence of family-labor enterprises even when they are involved in market-exchanges contradicts the classic Leninist stance that 'class polarization and enterprise homogenization' are the normal form of agricultural development. This can only be understood as the outcome of adaptive peasant responses to capitalist expansion: '... the peasant holding, with its family labor and diversified, risk spreading output, will survive as a fallback position or "base", and will rarely be sold to outsiders' (p. 156). For De Janvry, the peasantry exist because they can be exploited. But for Lehmann, they can be exploited because they exist - their particular economic rationality makes them vulnerable to (market-) exploitation. Peasants, for example, will produce over price ranges that would entail negative profits for capitalists. 2.5.3. Semi-feudal relations of production Yet another position, frequently identifying the mode of production as 'semi-feudal', is that the exploitative relationship in which the bulk of the producers are involved may block the advance of the productive forces even though surplus generated is (potentially) large. Typically, the argument posits multiple channels of surplus appropriation from the direct producers particularly in the forms of (share) rents, usurious interest on consumption credit

54

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

and unfavorable conditions of sale for the commodity [Bhaduri (1983)]. Direct producers deal not with an impersonal market but with a monopolistic landlord who is also lender and trader. Under certain conditions, it is in the interest of this exploiting class to maintain these 'semi-feudal' relationships rather than enhance productivity. This view has been advanced most frequently for eastern India and for parts of Latin America. Prasad (1974) found it to be relevant in Bihar where he found such semi-feudal landlords making little effort to exploit available opportunities for irrigation or electrification. Chandra (1974), while accepting the descriptive validity of semi-feudal relations of exploitation, does not find that productive investments have been impeded by such relations. Widespread unemployment permits landlords to enhance rents and/or interest charges, and to keep the producers poor and dependent even with productivity increases. Instead, he views the restriction on aggregate demand due to unemployment and poverty as the major reason for low rates of accumulation which in turn reproduces unemployment and semi-feudal relations.

2.5.4. A simple dichotomy of classes Rudra, an early protagonist in the mode of production debate, recently rejected the concept of mode of production on grounds that it is inadequately formulated and leads to useless proliferation of alternatives such as feudal, capitalist, semi-feudal, transitional, colonial, dual, etc. [Rudra (1978)]. Similarly, he finds 'dominance' among modes or contradictions between them ill-defined. He prefers to characterize agrarian classes on the bails of their contradictory relations to the means of production. For India, he finds that there are only two classes in this sense: the exploiting class including landlords, rich peasants, large tenant farmers, traders and moneylenders, and the exploited class including landless laborers, petty producers and tenants. Although the exploiting class may reveal different degrees of capitalist or non-capitalist behavior, there need be no contradiction within that class. Using Indian data pertaining to various regions he denies that (a) sharecropping and indebtedness are sure signs of non-capitalist economic relations, (b) the increase in wage-labor and decline in tenancy indicate capitalist development, (c) technological scale economies are generally prevalent, and (d) the growth in farm size and in mechanization is symptomatic of a radical change in class relations. Bardhan (1979), while agreeing with the bulk of Rudra's thesis, finds empirical cause to disagree with Rudra that a middle peasant 'class' does not exist. He finds that a middle peasant group - who neither hire-in labor nor hire-out - are in fact important in many parts of the country. Following Rudra's definition, he argues that they are a 'class' that relates to Rudra's

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

55

classes in predictable ways: they ally with landlords on land reforms but not on the issue of public subsidies (which are likely to be monopolized by the landlords). He also rejects the notion that capitalist and feudal elements can coexist without contradiction: 'feudal' control of labor, extensive use of land and 'unproductively' employed capital are bound to fetter capitalist growth. Empirically, Bardhan notes that productive investments are growing, that land is increasingly concentrated among larger and progressive farmers and that wage-labor has grown particularly at the expense of the middle peasantry. Therefore, he finds it 'hard to agree with Rudra that the emerging capitalist or semi-capitalist relations are not replacing feudal relations' (p. 860). 2.5.5. Market power and control of the labor process Finally, there exists a class of explanations for 'connectedness' in the labor market that focuses on problems in labor exchange and/or in the labor process. Recently, a closer analysis of the size-productivity link has revealed that a simple interpretation in terms of unemployment and labor cost dualism between 'capitalist' and 'peasant' farms is by itself insufficient. The earlier studies of Rudra and others [see Chattopadhyay and Rudra (1976)] had cast doubt on this interpretation through the findings that (a) there was no significant relationship between labor intensity and the share of family labor in total labor input, and (b) there was a significant inverse relationship between size and labor intensity even on hired-labor farms. Ghose (1980) has produced some evidence suggesting that the latter findings may be a reflection of oligopolistic power in the labor market: he found that the concentration ratio in terms of hired labor across his sample farms was high. The observed inverse relation for labor-hiring farms may then reflect leader-follower behavior in the wage-labor market. On the other hand, Sen (1981) argues that the major constraint on labor-hiring may be the availability of family labor on the assumption that hired labor requires to be supervised by family labor. He uses statistical correlations to support his claim that the two types of labor are, in fact, complementary. It should be noted that the oligopsony explanation can be squared with the assumption of unemployment only by supposing further that labor markets are segmented. While the family supervision explanation requires no such elaboration of assumptions about the labor market, the complementarity between family and hired labor that it requires is not particularly plausible. Both explanations imply that increased employment potential created by technological developments will not be fully realized: labor absorption on labor-hiring farms will be restricted for reasons of market power or of family labor constraints. It may therefore be foreseen that small farms will be compelled by poverty and unemployment to intensify labor-use and remain semi-proletarians.

56

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

By way of conclusion, the main points of this section are highlighted: First, it is fair to say that recent analyses of contemporary experience have largely eclipsed both the simple Chayanov and the simple Leninist positions regarding the peasantry. The peasant mode of production is neither isolated/ stable nor entirely subordinated/disintegrating in relation to the rest of the economy. The persistence of the peasantry has to be understood as a consequence of a complex set of forces including peasant rationality, the pace of economic growth, state policy and the mechanisms by which peasants and proletarians are exploited. The ways in which these forces act and interact are not, however, fully understood. Second, rural labor markets are characterized by chronic or, at least, seasonal unemployment. Rural wages are therefore determined, in large part, by institutional forces. These forces should be understood to include both micro- or village-level elements (contradictions in the labor process, local power and 'moral' imperatives), and macro-level interactions such as the pace of accumulation, technological changes, state policies, etc. Third, resource allocation and use are significantly dependent on production organization and wealth distribution. Though markets in labor, land and credit may work to weaken these links, the influences of asset inequality and the nature of the enterprise persist strongly. These are not reducible to market imperfections, although market power may be a significant influence in its own right. Together with the preceding point, it is evident that the neoclassical approach to allocation and distribution is called into question. Finally, outside of the neoclassical approach, several interesting though not necessarily mutually consistent formulations of agrarian modes of production have emerged. Much work remains to be done within each framework - by way of refining theoretical propositions and providing enough empirical substance - before they can be compared and evaluated. But few can doubt that these formulations represent serious attempts to understand the emerging situation in Third-World agriculture.

3. Patterns of surplus appropriation The preceding section has highlighted conflicting approaches to the analysis of agrarian dualism and of rural labor markets. The link between wealth distribution and resource allocation, according to the Marxian/ structuralist approach, arises not merely because wealth concentration gives rise to unemployment and contradictions in the labor process, but also because it is the fundamental source of problems associated with resource allocation through markets. Whether or not the capitalist mode of production is regarded as dominant in peripheral agriculture, it cannot be denied that analysis of market processes alone is insufficient to understand economic outcomes. Needless to say, these conclusions a r e routinely denied or ignored

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

57

in favor of a neoclassical model of rural markets, factor rewards and enterprise homogeneity. It should be no surprise, then, to find those conflicting positions reproduced, though in subdued form, when analysis shifts from the labor market to the land and credit markets. The importance of rural markets in land and credit derives both from the numerical significance of 'peasant' enterprises and from the widespread practice of renting or loaning of the means of production. Surplus is therefore extracted from direct producers (including the economically dependent peasantry) not only in the form of profits from employing wagelabor but also in the form of land rents, interest on loans, and trading profits. The determinants and consequences of these forms have been a subject of intense research in the past decade and a half. First, as regards the land market, the key questions have been (a) what circumstances contribute to owner-cultivation rather than renting-out?, and (b) why if renting-out occurs, may it be in the form of output-sharing arrangements rather than fixed-rent payments? Analysts have, by and large, sought economic explanations for the differential and simultaneous incidence of wage-labor, sharecropping and fixed rents and rejected the view that arrangements such as sharecropping reflect the hold of tradition. Second, in the credit market, competing explanations have emerged for the frequently observed fact of very high interest rates on borrowings. Finally, a number of papers have appeared to account for the phenomenon of linked transactions - particularly, in land, labor and credit between the same parties. This is also related to the existence of 'personalized' arrangements reflecting monopoly power or fragmented markets. Predictably, the bulk of neoclassical research seeks to establish that such markets do what markets are supposed to do - increase the welfare of the transacting parties, enlarge the social pie and achieve economic efficiency if only of the second-best variety. This view is opposed by other approaches that emphasize monopolistic and power relations in such markets and/or the limits to the efficacy of markets imposed by the class structure.

3.1. Competitive models of sharecropping Byres' (1983a) exploratory essay about, the incidence of sharecropping in various parts of the world reveals a long and checkered history of this form of surplus extraction. It also provides some clues why the search for a generally applicable and testable theory of sharecropping may prove futile: sharecropping has existed under a variety of objective (or easily observed) circumstances so that distinguishing its incidence on their basis is virtually impossible. It is interesting that recent theories of sharecropping have tended to rely on subjective or difficult to observe circumstances such as supervision

58

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

problems in the labor process, varying husbandry skills of producers, information costs and associated moral hazards, and wealth-dependent attitudes to risk. The reason for this is probably less that recent analysts were fully aware of the historical circumstances in which sharecropping has existed than that competitive models of sharecropping posed theoretical conundrums. At the center of theoretical debates about sharecropping has been its alleged inefficiency relative to wage-labor and fixed rents. Following the socalled 'Marshallian' view, some authors maintain that since the sharecropper secures only a fraction of output, his marginal returns to variable inputs including labor will be only a fraction of their respective marginal products. He would therefore employ less of these inputs than if he were a fixed-rent tenant or an owner-cultivator. At the same time, the tenant will seek to increase leased-in area as long as its marginal product is positive for such extension always yields him positive returns. Johnson's (1950) early article on the subject found this last implication of the Marshallian view implausible. He hypothesized that landlords would seek to redress this situation by a variety of means including direct enforcement of the optimal input intensities and the threat of eviction implicit in short-term leases. Cheung's (1969) work challenged the 'traditional' view that sharecropping suffered from allocational inefficiency. His main point was that, apart from the rental share, sharecropping contracts in practice do specify input intensities. He offered a model in which, subject only to the constraint that the tenant gets at least his alternative earnings as a wage-laborer (with the wage exogenously given), the landlord decides on the plot-size, the rental share, and the labor-intensity of tenant cultivation. The resulting 'competitive' equilibrium is easily shown to be indistinguishable from the fixedrent or wage-labor modes in its allocative and distributive outcomes. Cheung's rationale for the existence of sharecropping relied on its alleged superior capacity to permit risk-sharing between tenant and landlord. The wage system imposes all risk on the landlord, while under fixed rent the tenant bears the risk. However, it has been shown that this risk-sharing advantage of sharecropping is spurious since the same result could be attained by a suitable combination of the fixed-rent and wage-labor system, provided risk-sharing can be replicated without imposing technological (scale) diseconomies [Newbery (1977)]. Cheung's 'equivalence' theorem thus generalized leaves his approach with no rationale for sharecropping. Equivalence of outcomes, moreover, hinges on the feasibility of enforcing optimal intensities. But this is an empirical issue and no convincing evidence has been adduced in favor of the equivalence argument. Indirect efforts to test the relative efficiency of sharecropping have yielded mixed results. A few studies indicate that sharecroppers are not any less productive than owner-

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

59

cultivators or fixed-rent tenants. It has been argued that such results are based on weak tests of the disincentive hypothesis and may suffer from specification or simultaneity basis in the presence of the inverse relation between farm-size and productivity. When these are properly accounted for sharecropped land is significantly less intensively cultivated than owned land thus supporting the Marshallian argument [Sen (1981) and Caballero (1983)]. Bardhan and Srinivasan (1971) sought to restore the Marshallian view with the help of a general equilibrium competitive model. This was distinguished from Cheung's work chiefly in permitting tenants marginal choices in terms of labor supplied between the tenancy and working for wages: the Cheung model does not allow the tenant such marginal choices. Although this model preserves the incentive inefficiency of sharecropping, equilibrium requires that the marginal product of land be zero - a condition that poses a problem for the existence of equilibrium [Bagchi (1973)]. There is a measure of agreement now that sharecropping can only be understood (within a neoclassical setting) by elaborating models with enforcement costs, imperfect or non-existent markets, information costs and uncertainty - without these, as noted above, the Marshallian ('competitive') approach runs into an existence problem while the Cheungian ('competitive') approach is bereft of any explanation for sharecropping. As Newbery (1975a) had argued, share tenancy equilibrium will not be competitive in the conventional sense because the price system is incomplete with such contrasts. Restrictions on choices have to be added, although the forms such restrictions assume may differ. The disincentive hypothesis, though, remains a bone of contention among alternative theoretical elaborations of the Marshallian and Cheungian approaches.

3.2. Contractual forms in a full employment setting A number of recent models of sharecropping still seek to rationalize it within a full employment setting. Pant (1983) has constructed a model along the lines of Bardhan and Srinivasan (1971) but with added features that eliminate the existence problem: (a) entry into tenancy is restricted by the possession of non-traded inputs such as management skills and bullock labor so that there can be no excess supply of tenants, and (b) each tenant has a finite demand for land because land preparation requires a fixed amount of labor per acre. A Marshallian equilibrium is then shown to exist for CobbDouglas production functions. The tenancy arrangement emerges, despite its inefficiency, as an implicit trade of land for labor and non-traded inputs. Note, however, that fixed-rents tenancy is a superior alternative in these circumstances but is arbitrarily ruled out. Within the Cheungian tradition, i.e., where there are no costs involved in

60

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

enforcing optimal labor intensity, Newbery and Stiglitz (1979) have shown that, although production uncertainty per se is insufficient to give sharecropping an advantage, where there is an additional independent source of risk - the example emphasized is wage-rate uncertainty in the labor market sharecropping does provide additional risk-sharing benefits which cannot be replicated by a mixture of fixed-rent and wage contracts. Contractual forms may also be linked with uncertainty where landlords are unable to determine their tenants' abilities. Rao (1971) argued that sharecropping would be the preferred arrangement under conditions of relative certainty while fixed rents would be preferred where the tenant's ('entrepreneurial') response to uncertainty is an important but unobservable determinant of production performance. Fixed rents permit the tenant to capture the returns to his entrepreneurial skill under such conditions. More generally, where workers differ in their farming skills, a mix of contract types may emerge to serve as screening devices. As they acquire experience, workers move up from wage-work to sharecropping, then to fixed-rent tenancy and finally to landownership [Reid (1979)]. The 'competitive' models thus far considered all assume that the wage is exogenously given. It is not true, as some claim [Binswanger and Rosenzweig (1984, p.54)], that they have nothing to say about the determination of wages and employment. Equivalence of outcomes for wage-workers and sharecroppers with the wage exogenously given implies that potential tenants can always find employment at that wage, i.e., full employment in the labor market is a basic assumption underlying all of them. They differ only in regard to the assumption made regarding enforceability of labor input under sharecropping, and in regard to the particular rationale for sharecropping that is favored (non-traded inputs, information costs, etc.). Where enforceability is not' simply assumed, competitive arbitrage (or equivalence) of factor rewards is ensured through contractual or monopolistic restrictions by landlords. These restrictions are not compatible with a purely competitive view of contractual determination. 6 3.3. Sharecropping with unemployment

From a Marxian perspective, the most widespread view about sharecropping is that it is a transitional mode of surplus appropriation 'between forms 6Some of the specific arguments for sharecropping can also be criticized. Models based on non-traded inputs do not provide any convincing economic reasons for their basic assumption: for example, do owners of plough teams become tenants because the animals are not traded, or do workers who are ('politically') favored with tenancy contracts come to own the animals? Models based on skill differentials of workers seem implausible in many parts of the world where differentiation is based on privileged access to land and credit, mobility is typically 'downward', not 'upward' [Sivakumar (1980)1 and where farming skills are not difficult to acquire in the ftrst place.

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

61

of agrestic servitude and the full commoditization of rural labor itself' [Pearce (1983, p. 45)]. In other words, sharecropping is thought to be typical of pre-capitalist but transitional modes of production. It may persist in the early stages of capitalist development when accumulation and technical change are slow in creating a developed wage-labor market, but 'there will be a tendency for such contracts to be superceded by others more appropriate to high rates of accumulation in agriculture' [Pearce 1983, p. 54)]. Pearce argues that the mode in which surplus is appropriated cannot, as neoclassical models assume, always be understood as the outcome of a market process of bargaining. Specifically, he suggests that where the means of production are highly concentrated and supervision is not too costly, wage-labor will be the dominant form. With relatively high supervision costs associated with wagelabor, sharecropping will be dominant. Supervision costs, however, are not independent of class relations and the extent of class dominance. Where landowners enjoy monopoly power or where employment opportunities are very scarce, then 'such costs are minimized as tenants or laborers endeavor to maintain the landowner's favor' (p. 60). Finally, where new technologies which substitute capital for labor arise to reduce supervision cost, sharecropping may yield to wage-labor [Byres (1981)]. More or less in this perspective, several explanations have appeared for sharecropping which combine unemployment in the labor market and the Marshallian disincentive hypothesis together with supervision problems or risk-aversion or capital constraints. The core of the argument is that, where chronic or seasonal unemployment exists, this may serve as an inducement for profitable sharecropping arrangements between landlords and small peasants who have surplus labor. Small family farms with a low opportunity cost for their labor - due both to unemployment and to non-marketability of some of their labor - may rent-in land and work it intensively [Bagchi (1973), Mazumdar (1975), Ghose (1980)]. Marshallian disincentives will show up as a gap in labor intensity between the owned and sharecropped parts of such farms [Sen (1981)]. But given the low opportunity cost of labor, yields and surplus appropriated may be larger than under landlord cultivation with hired labor. The key questions around this argument are: (a) why should such leasingout be on sharecropping terms?, and (b) what limits such tenancies given unemployment? One view is that the maximum rent under fixed-rent tenancy, given production fluctuations, may be very low for poor farmers [Mazumdar (1975)]. Mazumdar also implicitly assumes that only landowning peasants can become tenants. Martinez-Alier (1983) maintains that if the supervision problem is viewed as a relative reduction in effort under wage-labor, then, together with the wage-gap this favors sharecropping despite the disincentive. Tenancy is limited chiefly by landlord fears of land reforms heightened by their exposure as pure rentiers when they do not self-

J.D.E.-- C

62

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

cultivate. Sen's (1981) argument is similar in that sharecropping exists to ease the connectedness arising from unemployment and supervision problems of wage-labor. The extent of sharecropping is restrained, however, by capital constraints on tenants as they must share part of the working capital costs, an argument that applies a fortiori in the case of fixed rents. Thus, these non-neoclassical models of sharecropping, like their neoclassical counterparts, also imply that it serves to improve the efficiency of resource allocation. When combined with political or economic constraints on the expansion of tenancy, these models further concur with neoclassical models in viewing equilibrium with sharecropping as a second-best optimum. What distinguishes them, though, is that they accommodate both unemployment and the Marshallian disincentive in reaching these conclusions. On balance, I think, the evidence - pertaining to unemployment and the inefficiency of sharecropping, cited earlier in this paper - from contemporary backward agriculture makes these models more relevant than the neoclassical ones. However, these models remain incomplete in the absence of adequate explanation for the inclusion of certain groups and the exclusion of others. Hart (1984) has argued that rules of exclusion and selectivity are persistent and key mechanisms for social control exercised by rural elites. Such control is needed to assure social stability, protecting property rights and securing the elite's social position. 'The key mechanisms through which the patron/ employer seeks to influence the client/worker is the latter's perception of being in a relatively privileged position. Fear of jeopardizing this position is the motivating force which elicits compliance and which creates and reinforces relations of dominance and dependency' [Hart (1984, p. 24)]. Hart cites several micro studies in support for this proposition. 3.4. Connectedness, resource allocation and inter-linked transactions

Few studies have focused directly on the link between wealth inequality and the failure of markets to achieve anything like 'efficiency'. The empirical basis for the existence of this link or 'connectedness' was briefly touched upon in the previous section. Raj (1970) has emphasized the role of default risks and, to a lesser extent, monopoly in explaining it. Landlords prefer to lease-out to larger and better off farmers because leasing-out to petty producers exposes them to a higher risk of (wilful or involuntary) rent default in the presence of production fluctuations. But, curiously, when he considers the similar link in the credit market [Raj (1979)1 where petty borrowers pay very high interest rates, he rejects the explanation for high interest rates based on allegedly high loan default risks. He views usurious interest rates as a consequence of very high risk free rates caused by the unequal distribution of incomes and monopolistic rural markets in credit and

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

63

(seasonal) stocks for consumption. Lipton's (1979) essay on rural credit markets makes a strong case similarly that inequality is a major source of inefficiency. Sen's (1981) comprehensive approach to connectedness is based on supervision costs and moral hazards in the presence of uncertainty in both land and credit markets. But it is distinguished particularly by the heavy emphasis on credit market constraints faced by middle and poor peasants: these may be self-imposed due to 'safety' considerations (middle peasants) or by creditors to restrain over-eager borrowers (poor peasants). These credit constraints limit the peasants' ability to lease-in land which requires tenant participation in the supply of working capital. The result is to reproduce the connectedness (that arises in the labor market) in the land market as well. On the other hand, those who face no problem in access to land and credit are constrained by their limited ability to employ hired labor due to supervision problems. The isolation and fragmentation of rural credit markets is the basis of an analysis of 'usurious' interest rates in backward agriculture by Bhaduri [(1983, ch,5)]. Personalized credit transactions not only eliminate lender's risk but also, when combined with the undervaluation of non-marketable collateral that the borrower has to offer, actually impose a cost on the borrower in the event of default which may be high if the borrower places a high value on the collateral asset. Where borrowers are unable to pay the high interest charges, such transactions become a vehicle for the transfer of the borrowers' assets to the lender. Bhaduri views such compulsive indebtedness as a transitional phase in which the peasantry are gradually dispossessed of the means of production. Bhaduri's earlier model of 'semi-feudal' relations in which such credit transactions are linked with sharecropping arrangements has stimulated much interest both in his specific propositions and in the general phenomenon of inter-linked or personalized transactions [Bhaduri (1983, ch. 4)]. Bhaduri's central propositions are that (a) such linked arrangements are used not only to extract surplus but also to perpetuate the sharecropper's credit dependence on the landlord, and (b) the landlord may resist productivity raising improvements if the tenant succeeds in reducing his dependence on him as he shares the increase in output, particularly if the loss of interest income exceeds the landlord's share of the increase in output. 7 The model has been criticized chiefly on the ground that if the landlord (or landlords) can unilaterally withhold the innovation in their own interest, they ought also to have sufficient power to extract all the gains from the 7It should be noted that this model is different from the analysis of usury noted above because the 'semi-feudal' relation is reproduced over time whereas the 'usury relation' is purely transitional [Rao (1980)].

64

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

innovation and still leave the tenants dependent on them [Newbury (1975b)]. But this is a non sequitur. Bhaduri's model does make landlord power central to such relations but landlords do not have unrestrained power or hegemony. Thus they may already be extracting a monopolistic 'limit price' in terms of interest rates and be legally or socially prevented from raising rental shares. On the other hand, if the innovation requires a minimum amount of public inputs (for example, irrigation or extension services), they may well find it easier to collude to withhold the innovation by blocking the flow of these public inputs. In a series of models designed to explain the incidence of sharecropping and of inter-linked transactions, Bardhan [(1984b, ch. 10)] has incorporated both the landlord's monopoly (land concentration) power and seasonal unemployment or rigid wages. The lean season is one when the potential tenant faces unemployment and is also compelled to borrow to meet his consumption requirements. As with Bhaduri, the landlord is the source of consumption loans and of (sharecropping) tenancies, but he also cultivates some of his land with hired labor. Bardhan finds that, both theoretically and empirically, the incidence of sharecropping rises with seasonal unemployment and the labor intensity (in the peak season) of technology, but declines with production uncertainty. His models assume that the share-rent and the interest rate are both exogenously given. Though the similarities with Bhaduri's model are thus quite strong, the differences are sufficient to preclude a negative landlord response to innovations. In a related model [Bardhan (1984, ch, 5)] he has shown the existence of a negative association between the incidence of 'attached laborers' (to be distinguished from casual laborers) and the extent to wage-labor unemployment: durable labor contracts are a means of reducing wage and/or labor demand/supply uncertainty for both parties rather than a reflection of 'feudal' restrictions on economic choice. Where the supply of tenants is perfectly elastic at an exogenously given utility level and tenant effort cannot be directly enforced, Braverman and Srinivasan (1981) have shown that plot-size variations alone by the landlord serve to hold the tenant down to his alternative utility levels. The additional instrument of a tied tenancy-cum-credit contract is rationalized in situations where the landlord has access to cheaper credit than the tenant so that the tying arrangement is a way of retaining this advantage for the tenancy. Neither technological improvements nor partial reforms of tenancy or credit alone suffice to improve the tenant's well-being. It would seem, therefore, that in more 'flexible' market settings than the one analysed by Bhaduri, his arguments about a link between the pattern of surplus appropriation and stagnation ceases to be valid. However, both the empirical and the theoretical basis of such a conclusion remain an issue of active debate. Sen (1981), in particular, notes that personalized and inter-

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

65

linked transactions may improve static efficiency by relieving connectedness in the short run, but such relief remains partial in view of credit and supervision constraints on the have-nots and haves, respectively. However, the long-run effect is to reduce the ability of the middle group to accumulate and hence to restrict the spread of land-augmenting innovations and the growth of employment. Although by no means identical to Bhaduri's analysis, this line of thinking is very much in the spirit of his argument. Other recent contributions rationalize inter-linked tenancy and credit contracts as ways of minimizing the costs of monitoring tenant performance in the presence of uncertainty and moral hazard. The most general theoretical discussion along these lines not restricted to credit- and tenancy-tying alone is that of Braverman and Stiglitz (1982). The basic point underlying their model is that subsidized consumption credit (and other types of subsidy) serve as an instrument to elicit tenant effort. But as Hart (1984) has aptly noted, this only constitutes 'the "carrot" component of a strategy of labor control' (p. 16). As with the micro-theoretic sharecropping models, contract enforcement in these models of inter-linked transactions requires monopolistic or 'non-economic' restrictions. Braverman and Srinivasan (1981) assume that the landlord can prevent the tenant from working for other landlords or for wages after the contract has been agreed upon. Hart points out that the 'stick' component in landlords' strategy underlying the model of Braverman and Stiglitz (1982) is more subtle. She identifies it in the 'ways in which landlords attempt to deal with the problem of default. [Braverman and Stiglitz] show that a bankruptcy clause (whereby the tenant is "allowed to default on his loan whenever his income is sufficiently low") tends to decrease tenants' effort and, conversely, that subsidized credit will only have the desired effect if backed by a bonded labor clause which is unfavorable to the tenant. Implicitly, of course, this assumes that the tenant is unable to abscond' [Hart (1984. p. 17)]. To sum up this section, a basic point emerging from the survey of analyses of land and credit markets (and their inter-linkages) is that assumptions about the labor market and the labor process are critical. Theoretical analyses of sharecropping in a purely competitive full employment setting run up against problems of internal consistency or end up with no rationale for share tenancy. This has led several neoclassical theorists to focus their attention on problems in the labor process - information and enforcement costs - and on market failures - non-traded inputs, for example. However, these models rely on the full employment assumption and on monopolistic or non-economic restrictions by landlords. The non-neoclassical alternative assumes neither costless enforcement nor full employment but relies on market or non-market mechanisms of excluding potential tenants. These mechanisms of exclusion need to be analyzed further to complete the argument satisfactorily. In a similar vein, inter-linked transactions - parti-

66

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

cularly in land and credit - are best seen as reflecting constraints on the functioning of these markets imposed by class structure, market power and the labor process. But the notion that such transactions serve to restrict the advance of technology, productivity and employment is a matter of continuing research and debate. This is not simply a question of the nature of markets (rigid or flexible) and agrarian structure but also of the exercise of state power and of class conflict. 4. Accumulation and agrarian structure Recall that the classical Marxian formulations of capitalist accumulation relied on the technological and accumulation advantages of the capitalist enterprise over pre-capitalist modes of production. Within this framework, Marx and Lenin charted alternative paths along which the capitalist mode develops within agriculture. (1) As in the English case, a capitalist class may emerge consequent to the expropriation of peasant holdings on feudal estates. Capitalist farmers gain access to the land in return for a cash rent to the landlords and are free to appropriate a profit and accumulate by employing the labor of the dispossessed peasantry. (2) Along the so-called 'Junker road,' the feudal estate is gradually transformed into a capitalist enterprise: feudal bonds give way to a free class of wage laborers and the feudal landlord becomes a land-owning capitalist. (3) Finally, capitalism may develop from a petty mode of production along the so-called 'farmer road'. A large class of land-owning peasants may exist initially as a result of colonization or radical land reforms. Social differentiation of such a peasantry gradually transforms a minority of them into capitalist entrepreneurs while the rest are reduced to proletarian status. So long as the accumulation process is not constrained, all three roads converge on a capitalist transformation of agriculture [Marx and Engels (1968) and Lenin (1964)]. This view of the agrarian transition is beginning to yield to a more complex formulation emphasizing one or more of the following elements: (a) the variable strength of the peasantry, especially a class of middle-to-rich peasants capable of producing a surplus, in the accumulation process, (b) the potentially key role of the state in determining the possibilities for profitable investment within agriculture and the unequal access of rural classes to the resources of the state, (c) the weight of merchant and usury capital in holding back productive accumulation and transformation in agriculture, (d) the nature of conflicts within the labor process as well as over the shape of new technologies that govern the growth of employment and the distribution of the gains from growth. Current research points to two rather significant general propositions

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

67

which seriously qualify orthodox Marxian conceptions. First, social structure may be a major constraint on technological development and accumulation or, at any rate, a crucial determinant of the forms of technological change. The primacy of the forces of production over the social relations of production is thus questioned. Second, the state's role in the evolution of class relations and of technology, though very important, is centered primarily on 'economic' mechanisms rather than being openly political or coercive. This modifies the usual Marxian notion that the political-coercive element in primitive accumulation (i.e., class polarization and the creation of a developed wage-labor market) is crucial. While the majority of recent models of agrarian growth focus on class conflict in one form or another, a few emphasize sociological and technological barriers to accumulation. Economic models along essentially Weberian lines have been put forward to explain agrarian stagnation [Fei and Ranis (1966)1 and the consequences of enclosures in pre-capitalist Europe [Cohen and Weitman (1975)-1. Productive forces in agriculture may stagnate for want of an 'entrepreneurial spirit' or accumulation drive. Transition out of such a state hinges on exogenous changes in the psychology and needs of the elite who appropriate the surplus. Similar arguments had been advanced by some Latin American structuralists to explain the long stagnation of agriculture in that continent, and are still used to explain the continuing problems of agriculture there [Barraclough (1977)]. Although the landed elite appropriates large rents, it is not inclined to maximize profits or accumulate capital. Estates are cultivated extensively reflecting such behavior. It should be noted, however, that the consequences of such behavior are not easily distinguished from those of substantial monopoly power in the control of land or the hiring of labor: a profit-maximizing landlord with monopoly power may also be expected to use land extensively and to refrain from investing in land-capital. Agrarian growth may also be held back by a combination of external (political) and internal (technological) forces. In explaining why capitalist development was long delayed in France as compared to England, Brenner (1976) argues that the role of the state was crucial. Being interested in protecting and expanding its tax base, the state put its weight on the side of the peasantry in their struggle to secure freehold rights over the land. Subsequently, onerous state taxes kept peasant surpluses down while the parcellization of production organization precluded land consolidation which was necessary for the growth of production investment. In analysing the forms of capitalist development in contemporary agriculture, Lehmann (1982) notes that the coexistence of a socially differentiated peasantry and large-scale holdings is reason enough to warrant serious qualification of (a) the Leninist view that social differentiation leads to class polarization and peasant disintegration, and (b) the Chayanov concept of

68

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

an essentially stable peasant mode of production. As an alternative to both, he suggests 'new paths of agrarian capitalism' that are likely to be taken in these contexts: (1) A 'bourgeoisie of small entrepreneurs' or 'capitalized family farms' using both hired and family labor may come to dominate the countryside based on relatively easy access to land and modern technology but using considerable amounts of capital. (2) An 'involutionary' pattern in which large estates grow by accumulating capital which adds little to the growth of employment while small peasant farms proliferate without the advantage of access to credit or modern technology and are heavily dependent on wage employment of a temporary sort. The 'capitalized family farm' route has little in common with populist ideals of an independent peasantry and arises 'most certainly after the mass of the peasantry have been forced to migrate, by fair means or foul' (p. 159). Neither is the 'involutionary' pattern a realization of Lenin's prediction of capitalist development via peasant differentiation, for 'try as they might, the rich peasants can hardly be held up to be a capitalist class, or the dynamic factor in capitalist development, when they still live in the shadow of the great estates' (p. 159). Lehmann argues further that the 'involutionary' pattern will be far less favorable to growth than the 'capitalized family farms' route, though it may be more susceptible to politically and economically viable land reform programs. Lehmann's 'new paths' have the considerable merit of describing and allowing for certain observable tendencies in agrarian structure and peasant behavior. But, as he is well aware, the argument lacks a rationale for which of the two paths will be actually taken. The means, 'fair or foul', by which the peasant mass emigrates and the large farms disappear leaving the field open to the capitalized family farms, are not specified. Neither is it evident whether the involutionary pattern is cause or consequence of slow growth. Lehmann's position in this regard is that the path of evolution will be determined by the particular history of agrarian structure rather than by conditions pertaining to world trade or government policy; but this thesis remains to be worked out. In contrast, De Janvry's (1981) modified Leninist stance does emphasize the importance of (a) the manner in which agriculture relates to the industrial sector and is integrated into international trade, and (b) state investment and price policies towards agriculture in shaping the evolution of agrarian structure. Functional dualism (cheap labor) and cheap food policies together sustain rapid industrial growth. At the same time, the large-scale capitalist agrarian sector is articulated into the growth process as it produces

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

69

'luxury foods', industrial inputs and exports. Cheap 'wage food' imports keep down the growth of the peasant agricultural sector. In the Latin American case, according to De Janvry, selective suppression of agricultural prices, coupled with state handouts of 'institutional rents' to the estate sector, are a way of accommodating urban and rural capitalist interests largely at the expense of the peasantry and the proletariat. The central contribution of De Janvry's analysis is his demonstration that, in much of Latin America, such across-the-board policy bias in favor of the estate-capitalist sector was a general phenomenon. But it is by no means clear that agrarian transformation along such a heavily sheltered Junker road was the least-cost alternative for the urban capitalist interests. His case for an economic basis underlying the political alliance between rural and urban elites rests on the plausible conjecture that the gamut of state policies towards agriculture was necessary for the continued reproduction of a reserve army of labor. This is a complex point to establish empirically and has been questioned by Lehmann (1982) and Caballero (1984a). Caballero notes, that in addition to the fact that labor demand has not grown apace with capitalist development, capitalism is not absolutely dependent on the peasantry as a source of the reserve army. A semi-proletarian peasantry may yet survive because capitalism c a n n o t easily replace them with capitalist production. But De Janvry's conjecture is not without precedent in the development literature. Lewis (1954) made a similar point concerning the logic of state policy towards agriculture and the nature of capitalist interests in it: 'The fact that the wage level in the capitalist sector depends upon earnings in the subsistence sector is sometimes of immense political importance; since its effect is that capitalists have a direct interest in holding down the productivity of the subsistence workers. Now, the owners of plantations have no interest in seeing knowledge of new techniques or new seeds conveyed to the peasants, and if they are influential in the government, they will not be found using their influence to expand the facilities for agricultural extension' (p. 411). Bardhan (1973) applied the standard Lewis model to explain the likely distributive impact of capital accumulation within an agrarian economy. Analogously with Lewis, the economy is divided into capitalist and peasant sectors with the supply price of (peasant) labor to capitalist farms determined by the average labor product of peasant farms - a condition that generates the inverse relation between farm size and land yield. Although this 'wage gap' handicaps the capitalist farm, it possesses a dynamic advantage in that (a) it invests its surplus in expanding land-capital, and (b) it secures landaugmenting inputs such as fertilizer at lower (and declining) cost than the peasant farm. As land-capital accumulates within the capitalist sector, it is shown that even though peasant incomes rise in absolute terms, the income share of the capitalist sector rises.

70

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

Note that if this process continues long enough, the measured inverse relation between yield and land area will tend to disappear and even reverse itself. This appears to be consistent with recent evidence on ithe sizeproductivity relationship in the 'green revolution' regions of India [Roy (1981)]. It is widely believed that though the new technology is scale-neutral, large farms have enjoyed superior access to credit, information and inputoutput price subsidies. A persistent feature of agricultural development in India has been its extremely uneven incidence across regions. The pace of agricultural growth is broadly correlated with certain aspects of agrarian structure: notably, the regions of rapid growth are in the erstwhile 'raiyatwari' (roughly, peasantdominated) areas, especially north western India, while backward agricultural regions predominate among the erstwhile 'zamindari' (roughly, landlorddominated) area, especially eastern India. Using cross-section information at the all-India level, Bardhan (1981) concluded that in regions with relatively high investment in agricultural fixed capital, the extent of proletarianization was smaller (e.g., northwestern India). A similar analysis with district-level information for contemporary West Bengal revealed, however, that there was an inverse association between the level of agricultural development and the relative significance of the independent family farmer class. Bardhan surmizes that these conflicting correlations could be explained by certain demographic and ecological characteristics. Proletarianization is high in regions with fertile soils and high population density (e.g., eastern India) and low in regions with low population density. Subbarao (1984) interprets broadly similar evidence as reflecting a kind of 'internal colonialism' perpetrated through state policies. The advanced/ capitalist regions enjoy disproportionately large shares of public investments, input subsidies and the marketed surplus of those crops for which government support price policies have been highly favorable. The backward regions are characterized as being given to subsistence production and peasant farming, and politically powerless. Government policies divert both private and public investable, funds to the surplus-growing regions. This argument is basically indistinguishable from those of De Janvry and Lewis cited earlier. Its applicability to eastern India, however, is surely disputable because that region is characterized by high land concentration and surplus appropriation in the form of rents, interest and trading profits. It is possible, though, that such policies, while harmful to the laboring classes in the backward regions, nevertheless benefit the rentiers in those regions. This is a plausible inference to be drawn from some of Bhaduri's l-(1983, ch. 7)] analytical work which he intended to apply to explaining agricultural backwardness in eastern India. In one formalization of his argument, Bhaduri considers two classes which appropriate the surplus from producers: a class of wealthy agriculturalists which engages in production-

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

71

augmenting accumulation and another class of merchants and moneylenders engaged in 'forced commerce'. This latter consists of 'unproductive' investments which merely change the distribution of output in favor of the investing class at a constant (or even declining) level of output. Investments by each class may have positive or negative spillover effects on the returns to the other class. Using this framework, Bhaduri classifies possible dynamic outcomes which depend on whether these two types of investment are complementary, competitive or both. In equilibrium, the two classes may coexist or one of them may be eliminated. His substantive point is that, in eastern India, the considerable strength of 'unproductive' channels of investment may have held back productive accumulation. In northwestern India, the rich peasant class had been strengthened by a series of reforms which provided the basis for rapid agricultural growth. It is the emergence of conflict that is the key to agricultural growth: a conflict that can be turned against the 'non-productive' classes by suitable structural reforms in rural credit and marketing structures, and through public investments in infrastructure. The economic distinctions underlying this appealing model of the pattern of accumulation and class relations, however, are ambiguous. In particular, this applies to Bhaduri's notion that investments in moneylending and trade are 'unproductive' activities that do not add to productive capacity - a notion shared by others [Rudra (1978)]. A generous interpretation of this otherwise obscure proposition is that incomes derived from these activities are typically consumed away, or that such incomes are typically derived on the basis of monopoly positions which are used to profitably restrict the productive use of resources. Yet another model, emphasizing problems in getting labor out of labor power on capitalist farms, has been proposed [Sen (1981)] to explain the potentially dynamic role that the middle-to-rich peasantry can play in agricultural development. Sen also finds that interstate variations in agricultural growth rates are positively related to measures of the strength of 'middle' groups vis-~i-vis large landowners and capitalist farms. Unlike the latter, middle peasants can expand production easily as they do not face a supervision constraint on the use of hired labor. Land-augmenting investments and improvements by large farms will entail substantial investments in mechanization to overcome the costs of labor management. The pace of growth and its employment or distributional effects will thus be significantly influenced by agrarian structure. Byres (1981) has drawn attention, in a similar vein, to the likelihood that 'the distinction between biochemical innovations and mechanical innovations, to the extent that those who make it argue that technological innovations can be limited to the former, is a false one'. The very process by which the biochemical innovations are introduced favors large farms by virtue of their differential access to inputs and credit.

72

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

This then sets up strong pressures towards mechanization. This complementarity arises from problems in satisfying the increased demand for labor input particularly at certain critical points in the production cycle and of managing the labor process in these circumstances. Nevertheless, technological solutions may exacerbate conflict between workers and their employers. Such conflict is not easily resolved and will be a critical determinant of further developments. Capitalist development, it has been argued, may also be limited by a 'rent barrier' [Patnaik (1983)]. This barrier is likely to be high where petty peasants and semi-proletarians predominate, as in eastern India. With largescale unemployment, landowners can extract very high rents from such producers. Capitalists who seek a minimum return on their investments can compete for land with the pauperized peasantry only if they have access to a technology capable of producing a significant increase in surplus-per-acre: otherwise, capitalist accumulation will remain arrested. Dutt's (1985) model of landlord--capitalist conflict is closely related to Patnaik's argument. Peasants and capitalists lease land from landlords at the same (fixed) rent. Peasants are assured a subsistence level of consumption and have a surplus of labor. Capitalists are therefore free to hire-in their labor at a wage rate equal to subsistence. Capitalists employ capital which peasants do not; capitalists respond to higher profit rates by investing in capital, while landlords respond to higher rents by expanding the effective supply of land. Dutt shows that, provided peasants have a higher labor-land ratio than capitalists (basically, the inverse relation) a fall in the subsistence rate raises land rents and reduces capitalists' incomes. This will also slow down capitalist development in the long run - exactly as in Patnaik. Several other interesting conclusions relating to the distributional and growth impacts of various types of technological shifts emerge from the model. The basic one is that, in general, there is a conflict between the economic interests of capitalists and landlords. The long run is characterized either by rising rents and land expansion, or by rising profits and capital accumulation. These results hinge on the assumption built into the model that landlords always meet the subsistence bill in excess of that portion which the capitalists will meet. Even if landlords can be distinguished from capitalists by their lack of interest in production and capital investment, what rationalizes their status as residual claimants? Perhaps, an appeal to different psychologies - capitalists as economic men, landlords as 'feudal' patrons. Political-economic forces - rooted in agrarian structure and class interests - that may be responsible for poor agricultural performance, increasing rural unemployment and misery, remain a neglected area in the largely technocratic approach that informs much of the discussion about agricultural development in Third-World nations. The few innovative pieces of research

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

73

addressed to this issue and surveyed above raise questions which should be amenable to further research. The main thrust of these studies is (a) to shift the focus away from general allocative efficiency and technological imperatives to the role of power and what Amit Bhaduri has termed 'class efficiency', and (b) to recognize more complex development sequences than commonly entertained by theories - neoclassical or orthodox Marxian - of technological determinism. The relative importance of differences in access to the resources of the state vis-fi-vis differences in rates of private accumulation in the evolution of agrarian structure needs to be analyzed empirically and theoretically. Of equal interest, perhaps, is the study of mechanisms by which some groups are excluded from public resources. Such mechanisms are hardly limited to national-level policy-making; village- or local-level institutions through which political power and economic power are fused also need to be examined. There is also ample room for sharpening the empirical analysis of the connections between output and employment growth and agrarian structure. Perhaps, cross-country comparisons will be useful in this respect. The allegedly reactionary role of merchants and lenders - particularly the issues of peasant indebtedness and other forms of exploitation - needs further conceptual and analytical work. Finally, disentangling the technical from the social-conflictual bases of agricultural mechanization and other forms of technological development can be fruitfully pursued through micro-level studies.

5. The terms of trade

The terms of trade between agriculture and industry have historically occupied center stage in the political economy of industrialization and development [Mitra (1977)]. Movements in the terms of trade are believed to be an important determinant of the pace and patterns of long-run growth. This influence is exerted, often in contradictory ways, through changes in various 'surpluses' that agriculture is supposed to contribute to the development process: surpluses of labor, food, savings, foreign exchange and the government budget. But the magnitude and direction of these impacts depend critically on the specification of the macro structure and micro behavior of the economy. Conflicting assumptions regarding technology, agrarian structure, savings behavior of various classes, the process of price formation and foreign trade options give rise to competing views about the role of the terms of trade. Furthermore, their indisputable importance in effecting large shifts in the distribution of incomes makes the intersectoral terms of trade politically the most sensitive aspect perhaps of development policy.

74

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

5.1. Price incentives and production

A much debated issue is the response of aggregate agricultural production to changes in the terms of trade. This is not merely a question of private incentives and behavior but also of the nature of technology and agrarian structure as these shape the long-run response of agricultural investments and technological changes. Two broad positions may be discerned. (1) Some economists argue that agriculture faces 'unfavorable' prices in most LDCs [Schultz (1978) and Peterson (1979)]. The benchmark is usually 'the world price' following the static comparative advantage doctrine. In the belief that both private and public resources deployed in agriculture are highly responsive to price signals, unfavorable terms of trade are held responsible for slow agricultural growth. Problems of rural poverty, malnutrition, balance of payments disequilibrium and slow overall growth are supposed to follow this conjuncture. (2) Others are far less willing to accord relative prices such a pivotal role in agricultural growth. While acknowledging the importance of price incentives, they maintain that agricultural transformation is brought about by a complex combination of price incentives, changes in the social and institutional structure, and public investments in research, technological diffusion and rural infrastructure [Ishikawa (1967) and Krishna (1982)]. Studies of long-term trends in some East Asian countries support the second position. Hayami's (1972) study of Japan revealed that the real price of rice remained basically stable between 1880 and 1960. He attributes this to deliberate government policy designed to keep the wage costs of laborintensive industrialization low. Non-price policy efforts to raise yields through improving technology and infrastructure - served, together with declining fertilizer costs, to maintain agricultural output growth. Econometric estimates of long-run aggregate elasticities in agriculture, when based on the Nerlovian specification, are typically small (between 0.1 and 0.5). Other specifications of the formation of price expectations rational expectations, for example - do not alter this picture much. An exception is Peterson's (1979) analysis of yield responsiveness from cross-country (developed countries and LDCs) data for 1962--64 and 1968-70. His elasticity estimate was 1.66 or about five to ten times larger than the typical time-series number. Real agricultural prices in LDCs were found to be substantially lower than those in developed countries. There are numerous problems with Peterson's exercise but only one of these is singled out here for comment. Peterson himself acknowledges that the elasticity drops from 1.66 to 1.27 when research expenditure levels are controlled for. According to Chhibber's (1982) calculation, this is further reduced to 0.97 when a variable representing (public) irrigation is introduced.

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

75

The point is that cross-country estimation is highly inappropriate given the large number of country-specific variables determining agricultural supply. Schultz (1978) sees the allocative influence of price signals to be so pervasive as to determine even government priorities in public investment plans for growth. Specifically, it is maintained that if prices are low, government efforts in expanding infrastructure and research output will remain feeble. Note, however, that it is necessary, for this hypothesis to hold, that public resources are optimally allocated at existing prices. But such evidence as there is proves otherwise. Be it underinvestment in Philippines irrigation systems [Hayami and Kikuchi (1978)] or in Indian agricultural research [Evenson and Jha (1973)], the political economy of public investment is scarcely governed by the invisible hand. If what Schultz had in mind is the belief that LDC governments 'undervalue agriculture', then it seems plausible that they will undervalue agricultural research, public investment, etc. along with underpricing agricultural output. Such conjunctures often reflect powerful political forces shaping agricultural and related policies. Mitra (1977) and Subbarao (1984) have argued that the highly favorable price policy for wheat vis-h-vis rice in India was part of a policy of regional discrimination. The low levels of investment in infrastructure in the rice regions and of output in rice research reflect political/structural conditions in those regions and their political weight in the country rather than the influence of low prices. In a similar vein, it has been argued [De Janvry (1978)] that cheap food policies to promote importsubstituting industrialization cannot by themselves account for the pattern of agricultural development in Latin America, particularly Argentina: rapid labor-saving technological advance, a bias against yield-raising improvements and low output growth. Such a socially counter-productive pattern is secured by the class interest of the traditional elites who seek to control the entire institutional process by which technologies are generated and implemented so as to maintain land values and rents. Reasons for the weak efficacy of prices in influencing agricultural supplies are not far to seek. A major one has to do with the nature of technology and the associated necessity for state action while another is intimately related to constraints upon state action deriving from agrarian class structure. First, if there is significant complementarity between private and public inputs, price incentives alone cannot accomplish much. This seems to be the case at least in Asian agriculture [Ishikawa (1967)-]. Second, if surpluses need to be mobilized from agriculture to finance basic investments, the method of doing so will have an obvious influence on the yield from such investments. In much of developing agriculture, land or income taxes are notoriously difficult, largely for political reasons, to collect. Indirect taxation may then be resorted to. Therefore, viewing prices merely as private incentives is apt to be highly misleading.

76

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

Finally, where the government's capacity to provide for efficient planning and implementation of the prerequisites of development is weak, public choices about the right mix of price, investment and tax policies may be less potent then efforts to bring about deeper institutional changes. Once again, such failures need be neither generic nor accidental: they may be engineered by unholy alliances between private and public 'rent-seekers'. The preceding arguments all assume that a favorable shift in the terms of trade will increase the private investable surplus. Recent two-sector models in the Sraffa/Ricardo tradition suggest that this may not happen under certain conditions. Gibson and McLeod (1982) employ a Sraffa-type model to show that (a) with only produced inputs and labor in both sectors, an increase in agriculture's terms of trade will raise the agricultural profit rate, whereas (b) when agricultural production requires scarce land inputs as well, an exogenous rise (fall) in the price of the agricultural output (input) may actually decrease agriculture's profit rate. The authors conclude that 'to the extent that investment is related to changes in the rate of profit among sectors, the conventional prescription of higher prices as an antidote to agricultural stagnation must be qualified accordingly' (p. 32). This model supposes that the terms of trade are exogenously manipulated (presumably through trade or othe_r restrictions by the policy-maker). Dutt's (1985) model produces a similar result with endogenous prices (see also section 4). Promoting industrial growth in the hope that the agricultural sector will follow may not always work. This proposition (as well as the one due to Gibson and McLeod) is based on (a) conflict between agricultural profits and rents, and (b) the idea that landlords are uninterested in accumulation. Favorable movements in the terms of trade, as in Ricardo, are good for rentiers but not necessarily for growth. Conversely, as Caballero (1984b) has shown, trade between a capitalist industrial sector and peasant-dominated agriculture will involve 'unequal exchange' in favor of capitalists. The conclusion rests on comparing two economies with identical industrial sectors but with agricultural output produced by peasant enterprises in one and capitalist farms in the other. Peasants face lower implicit labor costs than capitalists and also have no access to investment opportunities. Exchange is characterized by lower terms of trade and the economy-wide profit rate is higher under peasant production than under capitalist production.

5.2. Distribution Partial equilibrium analyses - both theoretical and empirical - show that, for any given food price increase, incomes are transferred primarily from high-income consumers to high-income producers, and the relative deprivation is greatest for low-income consumers and for low-income producers

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

77

who are net buyers of food (in that order). Whether price increases result from supply shocks or from changes in government policy, the poor suffer unless something is done to restore their purchasing power. Clearly, the rural/urban dichotomy of interests fails to do justice to the cross-currents produced by differentiation within both rural and urban 'classes'. The short-term and long-term distributive (general equilibrium) effects of the terms of trade have been examined in Chichilnisky and Taylor (1981) and Taylor (1983). The agricultural sector in these models provides food to the industrial sector and (partially) finances the investment in that sector through savings flows. The industrial sector is constrained by aggregate demand for its output (with mark-up pricing) while agricultural output is fixed, in the short run, by land-capital constraints. As the terms of trade move in favor of agriculture, the demand for manufactured goods falls off from the urban sector while it rises due to increasd expenditures out of the increased income of the rural sector. If the agricultural sector is relatively small, a policy aimed at reduced food prices through increased food imports will also increase industrial output. Hence, the urban sector is doubly benefited - food prices fall and output expands. When such policies are sustained over a long period, they depress agricultural production and investments (note that rents and profits are not distinguished - both are sources of capital accumulation) and, therefore, tend to justify themselves - a conjuncture descriptive of Latin American countries where cheap food policies have been pursued. Such policies will be opposed by both rural and urban groups if higher rural incomes due to higher domestic food prices sustain high levels of industrial output - a configuration that is probably descriptive of India in the late sixties and throughout the seventies. In the long-run 'Cambridge' version of this model [Taylor (1983)], agricultural growth depends on non-shiftable capital goods produced by industry. If agriculture's growth rate is limited by technological or absorptive constraints, and if workers seek to defend their real wages by pressing for money wage increases, steady state growth will occur with positive inflation. Faster growth will not only push up the rate of profit but also the rate of inflation reflecting conflicting claims on output by workers and capitalists. Some of these propositions have been empirically studied using computable general equilibrium models. McCarthy and Taylor (1980) carried out food policy experiments using such a model for Pakistan. Removal of wheat subsidies (which chiefly benefit urban consumers) were found to reduce the real incomes of all consumers with the heaviest burden being on the poorer, especially urban, groups. The reduced budget deficit also leads to a contraction in real GNP. If the removal of the subsidy is compensated by an increase in government expenditure on non-agricultural products so as to leave aggregate income unchanged, then, although the nominal income distribution is affected very little, the rural and urban poor are adversely

78

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

affected as reflected by reduced wheat consumption and calorie intake. In another experiment, it was found that a fertilizer subsidy to wheat produces little benefit for the rural poor if the government does not also support the price of wheat. In a similar exercise for Bangladesh, Hossein (1984) has shown that changes in food supply and food prices have a large impact on real income distribution and the absolute living standards of the poor. As usual, income effects are far more important than substitution effects due to relative price changes in determining the extent of consumption loss of the poor when food prices rise. He also found that the adjustment of money wages to food prices is insufficient to mitigate the real income loss. Another study designed to measure the general equilibrium distributive impact of price policies on different regions and classes in India found that rich surplus-growing farmers in the technologically advanced states benefited most from price support operations by the government while landless laborers and poor consumers suffered real income losses [De Janvry and Subbarao (1983)]. 5.3. The marketed surplus The standard form which the terms of trade issue takes in the development literature is that of the marketed surplus of agricultural products. Rising food prices do not necessarily increase the amount of food sold by the country to the towns: low supply elasticities can conspire with strong income effects on food demand within agriculture to produce 'perverse' effects. As economic development proceeds, technology may be expected to develop along lines which increase the use of industrial inputs in agriculture, while rising farm incomes may be expected to alter farm consumption demand in favor of industrial goods, hence raising the flow of marketed surplus. But when income levels are low and, particularly, where food production is largely in the hands of small peasants, perverse responses are to be expected. Discussions of this 'wage goods bottleneck' which assume a static context may misdirect attention to the role of food prices. This certainly was the case in the early Sovlet industrialization debates. The impact of (biased) technical progress in agriculture on the speed of industrialization is the subject of a recent two-sector model in the Lewis tradition [Lele and Mellor (1982)1. Industrial employment is limited by the marketed surplus of food and, as in Lewis, the industrial wage is tied to average labor earnings in agriculture. Since the class distribution of incomes within agriculture is the crucial determinant of demand behavior, the authors conclude that industrialization depends on the distributive bias of new technologies. With limited substitution options (between land and labor) within agriculture, land-augmenting improvements reduce food prices and increase non-agricultural employment. This is brought about by a decline in the share of income accruing to agricultural labor.

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

79

A different approach to the issue assumes full employment but strong technological dualism between the sectors [Bell (1979) and Taylor (1979)]. Specifically, factor substitution possibilities are assumed limited in industry but large in agriculture. In an open-economy setting, capital accumulation in industry proceeds reasonably smoothly as labor supply responds elastically in the early stages of development ~i la Lewis and Eckaus. However, given suitable restrictions on internal demand behavior, an increase in the demand for agricultural exports may well result in a drop in export earnings. If the economy is closed to trade, similarly 'perverse' behavior shows up in the domestic market. Industrial expansion shifts the terms of trade against industry and profits get squeezed. Evidently, intersectoral interactions depend on the assumptions made about technology and agrarian class structure and on the 'closing rule' chosen for the macro model. As important as they are in theoretical models, these assumptions need to be tested against experience. Sadly, good evidence rarely drives out bad theory (especially when the theory supports comforting political/policy conclusions). Apart from supplying food to urban areas, agriculture is also supposed to contribute resources to capital formation elsewhere in the economy, particularly at low levels of income. Keeping agricultural prices low is expected to contribute to this process. This was, for example, Preobrazhenski's position in the Soviet debate. This proposition is not supported by evidence about early Soviet industrialization [Ellman (1975)] or by more recent LDC experience - although agricultural exporters and East Asian countries are exceptions. According to Lee (1971), agriculture in Taiwan was a major source of net saving for the rest of the economy during the first half of this century. The terms of trade were turned against agriculture throughout this period. A comparative study of Japan and India [Mody, Mundle and Raj (1982)] concluded that while resource flows from agriculture contributed significantly to industrialization in Japan during 1888-1937, during the corresponding phase of Indian development (1950-70), agriculture made no such contribution and may even have been a net recipient of resources. Recently, Taylor (1984) analysed patterns of intersectoral resource flows using data from social accounting matrices for about 20 LDCs. He concluded that resource flows out of agriculture were positive in most of them but accounted, as a rule, for only a small fraction of non-agricultural capital formation. The exceptions were agricultural exporters. The linked problems of the marketed surplus and resource flows have been analysed in an optimizing framework under conditions of steady growth [Hornby (1968)]. Hornby's model is not without policy significance even though the underlying political assumptions are perhaps naive [Taylor (1979, p. 173)]. Governments are thought powerful enough to set the internal terms of trade but not enough to collectivize agriculture or tax its incomes. The

80

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

government, it is also supposed, effectively controls the industrial surplus and allocates investable resources among agriculture, capital goods and industrial consumption goods (or, equivalently, chooses the terms of trade) so as to maximize growth. Optimal policy involves (a) relatively low food prices but significant capital allocations to agriculture when the marketed surplus elasticity is small, but (b) if the elasticity is large, the government invests little in agriculture but also exercises little of its monopsony power. Another interesting policy implication of this model is that free (external) trade is far from optimal in the former case, This is but one important example of numerous arguments that should be counted against the Schultzian free trade position. I should add that if it is naive to assume that governments freely choose the terms of trade, it is not any less so to assume, as the earlier benefit-cost literature does, that they are free to choose modern sector production techniques. In political economy terms, neither choice is free from the fundamental and contradictory influences of classes. Optimizing models cannot be expected to capture these influences and may therefore be largely beside the point.

6. The agrarian question: Towards a non-neoclassical approach To those who would maintain that the past two decades have witnessed a stagnation of development economics this paper offers little support. No doubt a picture of disarray is presented by the sheer diversity of positions taken by development practitioners and theorists. But critical evaluation and selection from this menu does reveal that new and significant advances are being made. Broadly speaking, this is evident in vigorous attempts to understand the structural determinants of the pace and pattern of growth, the role of class interests and conflicts and the political economy of state action. New directions in the analysis of the agrarian transition have been largely constructive in this sense. It is possible to recast some of these developments around certain questions that exercised the minds of economists since at least Ricardo and Malthus: questions that had spawned directly contradictory positions. These include (a) the fate of the peasantry (Lenin, Chayanov), (b) the economic role of the 'unproductive classes' (Malthus, Ricardo), (c) the terms of trade as an instrument in 'primitive accumulation' (Bukharin, Preobrazhenski), and (d) the rationale of 'precapitalist' arrangements such as sharecropping (classical versus neoclassical economists). New insights on each of these issues typically transcend or subsume the contradictory positions taken by earlier economists. To these should be added new research that has grappled with issues that are closely related to agrarian structure and its consequences: moral (or political) versus rational imperatives governing the village economy, struc-

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

81

tural as opposed to market determinants of contractual forms and their inter-linkages, technology versus the social relations of production as determinants of the labor process, etc. (1) Recent contributions to the mode of production debate, while still divided on alternative ways of characterizing agrarian classes and production relations, seem to have largely superceded the classical Leninist and 'populist' positions on the stability of the peasantry in the face of capitalist development. The persistence of the peasantry has to be understood as the outcome of a complex set of forces including peasant rationality, the pace of growth, state policies and the mechanisms by which surpluses are extracted out of peasants and landless proletarians. (2) The neoclassical approach to resource allocation and income distribution - stressing full employment, the absence of any link between inequality and resource use efficiency, and the irrelevance of enterprise forms - persistently ignores some basic features of contemporary agrarian economies. Backward agriculture does function with a developed wage-labor market but, as under capitalism, also produces a reserve army of unemployed comprised of the landless and peasant family workers. Rural wages are therefore determined, in large part, b y institutional/structural factors. Resource use moreover depends significantly on production organization and wealth distribution. Though markets in land and credit may work to weaken these links, the influence of asset inequality and enterprise forms persist strongly. (3) Neoclassical attempts to resolve the sharecropping conundrum (within a 'competitive' setting) have not been successful. Where the laborenforcement problem is not simply assumed away, available models are compelled to rely on monopolistic or 'non-economic' restrictions by landlords. Non-neoclassical arguments stress the role of unemployment and the labor incentive/enforcement problem in determining the incidence of sharecropping but rely on market rigidities (capital constraints on peasants, for example) or non-market factors by which potential tenants are excluded/ selected. Theories of personalized and inter-linked transactions divide along the same lines as with sharecropping and reproduce the same assumptions and problems. But the idea, due to Bhaduri, that such transactions serve to restrict the advance of productivity is a matter of continuing research and debate. (4) Ricardo's notion that landlords or rentiers slow down the process of capital accumulation seems to be alive and well in a variety of forms. A powerful rentier class - including landlords, merchants and moneylenders- is viewed as having economic interests that are often in conflict with the accumulating class directly interested in production within agriculture (be they capitalists or surplus-producing middle peasants). But the models

82

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

producing such results draw, perhaps, too sharp a line of distinction between the 'progressive' and the 'unproductive' classes. A different line of thinking stresses the superior access of rentiers-cum-capitalists or 'Junkers' to the resources of the state in the accumulation process and produces the Ricardian conclusion in modified form: such access weakens the peasantry, distorts the pattern of development and slows down the growth of employment (if not of output as well). (5) The link between rentiers and capitalists has also been recast in the form of a structuralist macroeconomic model involving agriculture and industry. The answer to the debate between Malthus and Ricardo on whether landlords' rents stimulated or retarded aggregate demand is seen to turn on how wage-earners divide their incomes between the two sectors, following Engel's Law. (6) Historical and empirical analysis of the role of price incentives in agricultural production fail to support the position of 'price mechanists' such as Schultz. The prescription of higher prices as a way out of agricultural stagnation is of dubious relevance in most LDC contexts. For one thing, a rentier-dominated agriculture may respond 'perversely' to improved terms of trade. For another, such a prescription fails to take account of the leading role that public investments often play in agricultural development. A favorable movement in terms of trade, given political obstacles to taxation, may therefore slow down growth or lead to a distorted pattern of growth by accentuating structural dualism within agriculture. It has also been shown that the macroeconomic and distributive impacts of price adjustment may be unpleasant and politically unpalatable. (7) The protagonists in the Soviet industrialization debate as well as earlier development economists viewed agriculture's contribution to development in a static framework. They failed to perceive the essential function of investments and new technologies within agriculture in long-run growth. This framework tended to misdirect attention to the problem of fixing food prices alone, while putting aside the far more difficult tasks involved in the dynamic transformation of agriculture, particularly the role of class structure, private accumulation and public investment. Allowing for the technological and structural transformation of the agrarian economy points to more complex policy 'solutions' to the problem. But the issue cannot fit within any kind of optimizing policy framework whatsoever. What it calls for, instead, is the sort of thinking that underlies recent contributions summed up in this section. If these contributions together point to one thing, it is that there can be no political economy of development without a political economy of the agrarian question.

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

83

References Bagchi, Amiya K., 1973, Some implications of unemployment in rural areas, Economic and Political Weekly, Special number, Aug. Banaji, Jairus, 1976, Summary of selected parts of Kautsky's 'The agrarian question', Economy and Society 5. Bardhan, Pranab K., 1973, A model of growth of capitalism in a dual agrarian economy, in: J.N. Bhagwati and R.S. Eckaus, eds., Development and Planning (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA). Bardhan, Pranab K., 1979, On class relations in Indian agriculture: A comment, Economic and Political Weekly, May 12. Bardhan, Pranab K., 1981, Agrarian class formation in India, Journal of Peasant Studies 8, 73--94. Bardhan, Pranab K., 1984a, Determinants of supply and demand for labor in a poor agrarian economy: An analysis of household survey data from rural West Bengal, in: Hans P. Biswanger and Mark R. Rosenzweig (1984). Bardhan, Pranab K., 1984b, Land, labor and rural poverty: Essays in development economics (Columbia University Press, New York). Bardhan, Pranab K. and T.N. Srinivasan, 1971, Cropsharing tenancy in agriculture: A theoretical and empirical analysis, American Economic Review 61, 48--64. Barraclough, Solon, 1977, Agricultural production prospects in Latin America, World Development 5, 459--476. Bell, Clive, 1979, The behavior of a dual economy under different 'closing rules', Journal of Development Economics 6, 47-72. Bhaduri, Amit, 1983, The economic structure of agricultural backwardness (Academic Press, London). Binswanger, Hans P. and Mark R. Rosenzweig, eds., 1984, Contractual arrangements, employment and wages in rural labor markets in Asia (Yale University Press, New Haven, CT). Bliss, Christopher J. and Nicholas H. Stem, 1978, Productivity, wages and nutrition, Journal of Development Economics 5, 363-398. Boserup, Ester, 1965, The conditions of agricultural growth (Aldine, Chicago, IL). Braverman, Avishay and T.N. Srinivasan, 1981, Credit and sharecropping in agrarian societies, Journal of Development Economics 9, 289--312. Braverman, Avishay and Joseph Stiglitz, 1982, Sharecropping and the interlinking of agrarian markets, American Economic Review 72, 695-715. Brenner, Robert, 1976, Agrarian class structure and economic development in pre-industrial Europe, Past and Present, 30-75. Brenner, Robert, 1977, The origins of capitalist development: A critique of neo-Smithian Marxism, New Left Review. Byres, Terry J., 1981, The new technology, class formation and class action in the Indian countryside, Journal of Peasant Studies 8, 405--454. Byres, Terry J., 1983a, Sharecropping in historical perspective, in: T.J. Byres ed., Sharecropping and sharecroppers (Cass, London). Byres, Terry J., 1983b, Sharecropping and sharecroppers (Cass, London). Caballero, Jose Maria, 1983, Sharecropping: A survey, Unpublished manuscript (Rome). Caballero, Jose Maria, 1984a, Agriculture and the peasantry under industrialization pressures: Lessons from the Peruvian experience, Latin American Research Review 19, 3--41. Caballero, Jose Maria, 1984b, Unequal pricing and unequal exchange between the peasant and capitalist economies, Cambridge Journal of Economics 8. Chandra, Nirmal K., 1974, Farm efficiency under semi-feudalism, Economic and Political Weekly, Special number, Aug. Chattopadhyay, M. and Ashok Rudra, 1976, Size productivity revisited, Economic and Political Weekly, Sept. 25. Chayanov, Alexander V., 1966, The theory of peasant economy (Irwin, Homewood, IL). Cheung, Steven N.S., 1969, The theory of share tenancy (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL). Chhibber, Ajay, 1982, Dynamics of price and non-price response of supply in agriculture, Unpublished manuscript (Stanford University, Stanford, CA).

84

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

Chichilnisky, Graciela and Lance Taylor, 1980, Agriculture and the rest of the economy: Macro connections and policy restraints, American Journal of Agricultural Economics. Cohen, Jon S. and Martin L. Weitzman, 1975, A Marxian model of enclosures, Journal of Development Economics 1, 287-336. De Janvry, Alain, 1978, Social structure and biased technical change in Argentine agriculture, in: Hans Binswanger and Vernon W. Ruttan, eds., Induced innovation (The Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD). De Janvry, Main, 1981, The agrarian question and reformism in Latin America (The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD). De Janvry, Alain and K. Subbarao, 1983, Agricultural price policy and income distribution in India, Unpublished manuscript (Giannini Foundation of Agricultural Economics, University of California, Berkeley, CA) Feb. Dutt, Amitava K., 1984, Rent, income distribution and growth in an underdeveloped agrarian economy, Journal of Development Economics 15, 185-211. Ellman, Michael, 1975, Did the agricultural surplus provide the resources for the increase in investment in the USSR during the first Five Year Plan?, Economic Journal 85, 844-864. Evenson, Robert E. and Hans P. Binswanger, 1984, Estimating labor demand functions for Indian agriculture, in: Hans P. Binswanger and Mark R. Rosenzweig (1984). Evenson, Robert E. and Dayananda Jha, 1973, The contribution of agricultural production in India, Indian Journal of Agricultural Economics. Feeney, David, 1983, The moral or the rational peasant? Competing hypotheses of collective action, Journal of Asian Studies 42, 769-789. Fei, John C.H. and Gustav Ranis, 1966, Agrarianism, dualism and economic development, in: Irma Adelman and Eric Thorberke, eds., The theory and design of economic development (The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD). Frank, Andrew Gunder, 1967, Capitalism and underdevelopment in Latin America: Historical studies of Chile and Brazil (Monthly Review Press, New York). Gibson, Bill and Darryl McLeod, 1982, Terms-of-trade policy in a model with non-produced means of production, Journal of Development Economics 10, 31-45. Ghose, Ajit K., 1980, Farm size and land productivity in Indian agriculture: A reappraisal, Journal of Development Studies 16, 27-49. Goodman, David and Michael Redclift, 1982, From peasant to proletarian (St. Martin's Press, New York). Hart, Gillian, 1984, Interlocking transactions: Obstacles, precursors or instruments of agrarian capitalism?, Unpublished manuscript (Boston University, Boston, MA). Hayami, Yujiro, 1972, Rice policy in Japan's economic development, American Journal of Agricultural Economics. Hayami, Yujiro, 1982, Agrarian problems of India: An east and southeast Asian perspective, Economic and Political Weekly. Hayami, Yujiro and Masao Kikuchi,!1978, Investment inducements to public infrastructure: Irrigation in the Philippines, Review of Economics and Statistics 60, 70-77. Hornby, J.M., 1968, Investment and trade policy in the dual economy, Economic Journal 78, 96-107. Hossein, Wahid, 1984, Income and price responses to changes in food availability in a lowincome economy, Unpublished manuscript (Dhaka University, Dacca). Ishikawa, Shigeru, 1967, Economic development in Asian perspective (Kinokuniya Bookstore, Tokyo). Ishikawa, Shigeru, 1975, Peasant families and the agrarian community in the process of economic development, in: Lloyd G. Reynolds, ed., Agriculture in development theory (Yale University Press, New Haven, CT). Johnson, D. Gale, 1950, Resource allocation under share contracts, Journal of Political Economy 58, 111-123. Krishna, Raj, 1982, Agricultural growth, price policy and equity, Paper presented at the Third Annual Agricultural Sector Symposium (World Bank, Washington, DC). Laclau, Ernesto, 1971, Feudalism and capitalism in Latin America, New Left Review. Lee, T.H., 1971, Intersectoral capital flows in the economic development of Taiwan, 1895-1960 (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY).

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

85

Lehmann, David, 1982, After Chayanov and Lenin: New paths of agrarian capitalism, Journal of Development Economics 11, 133-161. Leibenstein, Harvey, 1957, Economic backwardness and economic growth (Wiley, New York). Lele, Urea and John W. Mellor, 1982, Technological change, distributional bias and labor transfer in a two sector economy, Oxford Economic Papers 33, 426-441. Lenin, Vladimir I., 1964, The development of capitalism in Russia (Progress Publishers, Moscow). Lewis, W. Arthur, 1954, Economic development with unlimited supplies of labor, Manchester School, 400--449. Lipton, Michael, 1979, Agricultural risk, rural credit and the inefficiency of inequality in: J.A. Roumasset, J.-M. Boussard and I.J. Singh, eds., Risk, uncertainty and agricultural development (Agricultural Development Council, New York). McCarthy, F. Desmond and Lance J. Taylor, 1980, Macro food policy planning: A general equilibrium model of Pakistan, Review of Economics and Statistics 62, 107-121. Marglin, Stephen A., 1984, Growth, distribution and inflation: A centennial synthesis, Cambridge Journal of Economics 8, 115-144. Martinez-Alier, Jose, 1983, Sharecropping: Some illustrations, in: T.J. Bytes (1983b). Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels, 1968, Selected works (Lawrence and Wishart, London). Mazumdar, Dipak, 1965, Size of farm and productivity: A problem of Indian peasant agriculture, Economica 32. Mazumdar, D., 1975, The theory of share-cropping with labor market dualism, Economica. Mellor, John W., 1979, Food price policy and income distribution in low-income countries, Economic Development and Cultural Change. Mitra, Ashok, 1977, Terms of trade and class relations (Cass, London). Mody, Ashoka, Sudipto Mundle and K.N. Raj, 1982, Resource flows from agriculture and industrialization: A comparative analysis of Japanese and Indian experiences (International Development Center of Japan, Tokyo). Newbery, David M.G., 1975a, The choice of rental contract in peasant agriculture, in: Lloyd G. Reynolds, ed., Agriculture in development theory (Yale University Press, New Haven, CT). Newbery, David M.G., 1975b, Tenurial obstacles to innovation, Journal of Development Studies 11, 263-277. Newbery, David M.G., 1977, Risk sharing, sharecropping and uncertain labor markets, Review of Economic Studies 44, 585-594. Newbery, David M.G. and Joseph E. Stiglitz, 1979, Sharecropping, risk-sharing and the importance of imperfect information: in J.A. Roumasset et al., eds., Risk, uncertainty and agricultural development (Agricultural Development Council, New York). Pant, Chandrasekhar, 1983, Tenancy and family resources, Journal of Development Economics 12, 27-39. Patnaik, Utsa, 1983, Classical theory of rent and its application to India: Some preliminary thoughts on sharecropping, in: T.J. Byres (1983b). Pearce, R., 1983, Sharecropping: Towards a Marxist view, in: T.J. Byres (1983b). Perkins, Dwight H., 1969, Agricultural development in China, 1368-1968 (Aldine, Chicago, IL). Peterson, Willis L., 1979, International farm prices and the social cost of cheap food policies, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 12-21. Popkin, Samuel I., 1979, The rational peasant: The political economy of rural society in Vietnam (University of California Press, Berkeley, CA). Prasad, Pradhan H., 1974, Reactionary role of usurer's capital in rural India, Economic and Political Weekly, Special number, Aug. Raj, K.N., 1970, Ownership and distribution of land, Indian Economic Review 5, 1-42. Raj, K.N., 1979, Keynesian economics and agrarian economies, in: C.H.H. Rao and P.C. Joshi, eds., Reflections on economic development and social change, Essays in honor of V.K.R.V. Rao (Allied Publishers, Bombay). Rao, C.H.H., 1971, Uncertainty, entrepreneurship and sharecropping in India, Journal of Political Economy 79, 578-595. Rao, J. Mohan, 1980, Interest rates in backward agriculture, Cambridge Journal of Economics 4, 159-167.

86

J.M. Rao, Agriculture in recent development theory

Reid, Joseph D., 1979, Sharecropping and tenancy in American history, in: J.A. Roumasset, M.-M. Boussard and I.J. Singh, eds., Risk, uncertainty and agricultural development (Agricultural Development Council, New York). Rosenzweig, Mark R., 1978, Rural wages, labor supply and land reform: A theoretical and empirical analysis, American Economic Review 68, 847-861. Roy, Prannoy, 1981, Transition in agriculture: Empirical indicators and results (Evidence from India), Journal of Peasant Studies 8, 212-241. Rudra, Ashok, 1978, Class relations in Indian agriculture, Economic and Political Weekly, June 3 (I), June 10 (II) and June 17 (III). Schultz, Theodore W., 1964, Transforming traditional agriculture (Yale University Press, New Haven, CT). Schultz., Theodore W., ed., 1978, Distortions of agricultural incentives (Introduction) (Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN). Scott, James C., 1976, The moral economy of the peasant: Rebellion and subsistence in southeast Asia (Yale University Press, New Haven, CT). Sen, Abhijit, 1981, Market failure and control of labor power: Towards an explanation of 'structure' and change in Indian agriculture, Cambridge Journal of Economics 5, 201-228 and 327-350. Sen, Amartya K., 1966, Peasants and dualism with or without surplus labor, Journal of Political Economy 74, 425-450. Sivakumar, S.S., 1980, 'Efficient' small farm, demographic differentiation and 'iron chest' accounting system: Some aspects of peasantist economics, Economic and Political Weekly, March. Subbarao, K., 1984, Regional differentiation in Indian agriculture: Emerging contradictions and policy responses, Paper presented to a seminar on Marx, Keynes and Schumpeter on capitalism, Jan. 27-30 (New Delhi). Taylor, Lance J., 1979, Macro models for developing countries (McGraw-Hill, New York). Taylor, Lance J., 1983, Structuralist macroeconomics (Basic Books, New York). Taylor, Lance J., 1984, Resource transfers from agriculture, Unpublished manuscript (MIT, Cambridge, MA). Vergopoulos, K., 1978, Capitalism and peasant productivity, Journal of Peasant Studies 5, 445-465. Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1974, The modern world system (Academic Press, New York).