A. Statement of Easton's Theorem Suppose that in the preceding chapter we had taken Z to be
w x on,where n is a positive integer. Then a proof like that of
Theorem 7.1 would have given
l=Img(K,) # K(SC(dj)) for each m < n. Thence by Theorems 3.45-3.47, we conclude l=Img(Kn)I K(SC(6)).
(8.1)
A proof like that of Theorem 7.2 gives tImg(K,+ 1 ) = K(SC(K,N for
c1
(8.2)
2 n. A proof like that of Theorem 7.8 gives
k1mgWn) = K(SC(Img(Kn - 1 ) ) ) -
(8.3)
Finally a proof like that of Theorem 7.9 gives l=Img(Kn)= K(SC(Img(KJ))
(8.4)
for 0 s m < n. 127
128
8. THE GENERALlZED GCH-THE
BOUNDED CASE
Suppose we should take I = w x w,? Analogously to (8.1) we would conclude !=Img(K,) I K(SC(i5)).
(8.5)
Can we conclude analogously to (8.4) CImg(K,) = K(WImg(Kfn))) for 0 5 m < w ? The answer is that we cannot. Indeed, we cannot conclude this no matter what Boolean algebra we employ, since it can be disproved in set theory. This is done by means of Konig's theorem. Formula 3.16 on p. 177 of Bernays and Fraenkel [l] states the generalized form of Konig's theorem, as given by Ph. Jourdain. In words, this takes the following form. Let J be a nonempty index set. Let f and g be functions from J to cardinal numbers such that for each j E J we havef(j) < ~ ( j )Then .
To apply this to the case at hand, we take J to be w ,f ( j ) = K j , and . Then we have
g ( j ) = fc,
That is
Now suppose that 2UO
= K,
.
Then
N, < (N,)No
= (2Na)Uo = 2 N o x N o = 2 N o
- K,,
which is a contradiction. Carrying out the above argument in our model gives !=Img(N,) # N(SC(i5,)).
(8.6)
kImg(K,+,) I K(SC(i5)).
(8.7)
So by (8.5)
A . STATEMENT OF EASTON'S THEOREM
129
However a proof like that of Theorem 7.2 will give (8.2) for a 2 o. Hence we conclude bImg(K,+
1)
=W~(Img(~,)))
(8.8)
for 0 I m I o. Clearly one can push such results considerably farther. However the question immediately arises concerning in what other ways one can generalize GCH consistently with AxC and the set theory axioms. Can one have generally
2N"= N,+Z for instance? Even more generally, for what functions E can one have 2N"= KE(=)
(8-9)
for all ordinals a? The classical GCH says that this can be done when E(a) = a 1. Godel [ S ] has shown that GCH is consistent with AxC and the axioms of set theory. The axioms of set theory impose certain requirements on E. Thus the argument used in the proof of Theorem 7.9 implies the following requirement.
+
Requirement 1. If a and E(a) I E(P).
are ordinals and a I p, then
As we saw above, Konig's theorem implies certain additional requirements. We now formulate these in precise terms.
Definition 8.2. We write Cf(a) for the cofinality of a, namely the least cardinal B for which there is a function f such that