1. Weak Projectivity and Congruences Let a , b, c, and d be elenients of a lattice L ; if, for any congruence relation 0 of L, a = b (0)implies that c =d (O), then we can say that “a =b forces c = d”. It is necessary to understand “forcing” in order to study the structure of congruence relations of lattices; this will be accomplished in the present section. In Sect,ion 1.3 we proved that a = b (0)iff a n b E a v b (0) and so it is enough to deal with pairs of comparable elements. To simFlify our notation, let a/b denote an ordered pair of elements a , b of a lattice L satisfying b i a ; alb is called a quotient of L. (This notation obviously imitates quotient groups: GIH.) cld is a subquotient of a/b iff b d
<
Figure 1
Figure 2
either case we shall write alb-cld, and say that alb is perspective to cld. I f we want to show whether the perspectivity is “up” or “down”, we shall write a l b p c l d in the first case and alb \ cld in the second case. If for some natural number n there exist alb = eo/fo, el/fi, , e,/f,, =c/d such that e,lf,-ei+l/fz+,, i = O , . . . , n-1, then we shall say that alb is projective to cld, and write a l b = c / d . (Note that a/b z a l b with n = 1 and a/b-c/d implies that alb x c l d . ) Yrojectivity is the trnnsitive extension of perspectivity. Observe that alb Y c l d and a = b imply that c = d .
...
130
111. Congruelices end Idcrtls
Figure 3
Figure 4
The concept of projectivity is sufficient for the study of “forcing” in many large classes of lattices (for instance, in the class of modular lattices, see Section IV.1). I n general, however, we have to introduce somewhat more cumbersome notions : weak perspectivity and weak projectivity. Consider Figures 3 and 4 permitting the degenerate cases ai = c and b, =cl. If a = b (O), then al = b, ( 0 ) by Lemma 1.3.7; since aJbi -c/o?, a = b ( 0 )iniplies that c ~ (0). d Let us say that cld is weakly projective into alb iff we can get from c]d into a/b in finitely many steps as described in Figures 3 and 4. Figures 3 and 4 then should describe the concept cld weakly perspective into alb. It turns out however that a special case of Figures 3 and 4 suffices to describe the same. We write cld 4,alb iff b d and c = a v d ; similarly, eld p w a / b iff c 2 a and d = b Ac (see Figures 5 and 6). If c/d p alb or cld \, aJb, then c/d is weakly perspective into alb, in symbols, cld-, alb. If for some natural number n and cld =eo/fo, e i / f l . . . , en/fn=a/b we have eilflhWei+,lfi+l, i = O , . . , n - 1 , then c/d is weakly projective into alb, in notation, c l d z , alb. (Note that cld is weakly projective into cld with n = 1.) Weak projectivity is the transitive extension of weak perspectivity. Observe that neither weak perspectivity nor weak projectivity is a symmetric relation. The concept of weak perspectivity is due to R. P. Dilworth [1950 a]. The notational system we use is geometrically motivated. Many papers (starting with G . Gratzer and E. T. Schmidt [1958d]) use the notation [b, a ] -[d, c ] or alb -cld
.
cld -w alb
c/d \ alb Figure 5
.
131
1. Weak Projectivity end Congruences
for c/dZw a/b; t,hese notations appear to be more natural from a universal algebraic point of view and have the advantage of emphasizing the nonsymmetric nature of weak projectivity. The following elementary observation shows the equivalence of the various forms of the definition of weak projectivity.
LEMMA1. Let L be a lattice, a, b, c, d E L, b $ a, and d I c. Then the following conditions are equivalent: (i) cld i s weakly projective into alb. (ii) There i s nn integer m and there are elements eo, . . , ,em-l EL such that
pm(a, eo, . * * em-1) = C a d ~ m ( beo, , .. where the polynomial pm i s defined by 9
> em-1)
=d,
Pm(X, YO, * * * ~ m - 1 ) * . ( ( ( x A Y o ) v Y I ) ’ Y ~ ) ~* ** * (iii) There i s nn integer n and there are quotients cld = e& eJf& eilfl, e;/f; . ,eJf, =aJb such that e:/fl i s n subquotient of ei+llfi+i and ei/fi-ei/fi, for i = O , 1,. , . , 9
..
n-1.
REMARK.Condition (iii) is the definition of weak projectivity using Figures 3 and 4.
PROOF.Figures 5 and 6 are special cases of Figures 3 and 4 respectively; hence (i) implies (iii). Now let (iii) hold. Then for each i =0, 1, ,n - 1, either ei/fi 7 e;/fi or ei/fi \ e:/f:. In both cases,
. ..
ei=p4(ei+l, e:, f:, ei, f i ) , fi=P4(fi+1, e:, f:, ei, f i ) . Repeating these steps n times we get (ii) with m <4n. Thus (iii)implies (ii). Finally, let (ii) hold. Then aAeo/bAeo7 , alb, (aAeo)vel/(bAeo)VelL, aAeolbAeo, and so on; in m steps this yields that c/d=, alb. k
We shall write cld =, a/b iff Lemma 1 (ii) holds with rn = k. This is slightly artifioial. It corresponds to requiring that the series of k weak perspectivities end with 7 , and that 7 , and \, alternate throughout. Intuitively, “a = b forces c =d” iff cld is put together from pieces each weakly projective into alb. To state this more precisely, we describe @(a, b), the smallest congruence relation under which a = b (see Section 11.3).
THEOREM 2 (R. P. Dilworth [ 1950a]). Let L be a lattice, a,, b, c, d EL, b 5 a, d
ejlei+i=w alb, for 10 Grltzer
j=O,.
. .,m-1.
132
111. Congruences and Ideals
PROOF.Let @ denote the following relation on L: x = y (0) iff x v y =c and X A Y = d satisfy the condition of the theorem. We first prove that @ is a congruence relation by verifying the conditions of Lemma 1.3.8. 0 is reflexive since for any c L w e get c/c
p wavclbvc I,,alb. ,
It is also obvious that if al 2 a2 2 a3 and al = a2 (a),a2 = a3 (a),then al = u:)(a). Indeed, take the sequences establishing uI=a, (@) and a2= a3 (a); putting the two sequences together we get a sequence establishing ai = a 3 (@). Nowlet CEO!(@), c > d , and /EL. Let c = e o 2 e l > - - . 2 e m = d bethesequence d that is, e i / e i + l x w alb for i = O , , . . , m - - l . ThencAf=e,,Af> establishing c ~ (@), el/\/ 2 2 e,Af =dAf and eiAflei+lAf fweilei+lxw alb, hence eiAf/ei+lAfx,,, alb for i =0, . . . ,n - 1 ; this proves that cAf =dAf (@). Similarly, cvf E d v f (@). Thus by LemmaI.3.8, is a congruence relation. a EE b (.@) and so 0 is a congruence relation under which a = b. Now let 0 be any congruence relation satisfying a = b (0). It is easy to see that for x >y and u 2 w, x = y (0)and ulv w Wxly imply that u =v (0). By a trivial induction, x =y (0)and u/vxwx / y imply that u = w (0).So finally, let c = d (a), established by cvd = e0 2 el 2 * * 2 em =cAd. Since ei/ei+lxw a/b we conclude that ei=ei+l (@), for i = O , . , ,m -1. Therefore, by the transitivity of 0 , we obtain that c = d (0).This proves that (D is the smallest congruence relation under which u = b, and so @ =@(a, b). Let L be a lattice and H L? To compute @ ( H ) ,the smallest congruence relation 0 under which a =- b (0)for all ( a , b) E H , we use the formula (Lemma 11.3.2)
- -
.
-
= V ( @ ( a b) , I (a, b>EH),
and we need a formula for joins:
LEMMA 3. Let L be a lattice and let Oi, i C I , be congruence relations of L. Then a = b ( V ( O i I i E I ) ) i f f there i s a sequence zo = aAb I zl5 z, =avb such that for each j with 0
---
<
The proof of Lemma 3 is the same as that of Theorem 1.3.9, namely, a direct application of Lemma 1.3.8. By combining' Theorem 2 and Lemma 3 we get :
COROUARY4. Let L be a lattice, let H L2, and let a , b L with b< a. Then a ZE b ( 0 ( H ) )i f f for s m e integer n there exists a sequence a =co 2 ci 2 2 c, = b such that for each i, with 0 5 i < n , there exiats a (d, e) EN mtisfying
---
ci/c,i
d ve/dAe.
COROLLARY 5. Let L be a lattice, let I be a n idea,l of L, and let a , b E L , b
--
1. Wmk Projwtivit,y and
Congruences
133 0
Figure 7
Figure 8
Recall that, an ideal I is called the (ideal) kernel of a congruence relation 0 iff I is a congruence class modulo 0 (Section 1.3).
COROLLARY6. Let L be a lattice and let I be u n idenl of L. Then I i s a kernel of u congruence relation iff u/b=, c / d , u L, and
b, c, d I imply that a E I .
PROOF.Combine Corollary 5 with the observation that I is a congruence kernel of sotiie congruence relation iff I is the kernel of @ [ I ] . In distributive lattices every ideal is the kernel of some congruence relation, in fact this property characterizes distributivity. I n general lattices we shall introduce various classes of ideals that are congruence kernels for which @ [ I ] can be nicely described. This will be done and applied in Sections 2-4. In a sense, weak projectivity describes the structure of congruence relations of a lattice. It is not surprising, therefore, that many important classes of lattices can be described by weak projectivities. We give two examples. To introduce the first class, the class of weakly modular lattices, we need a lemma, for niotivation. LEMMA7. Let L be a lattice, ( I , b, c, d E L , b < a , d
--
PROOF.Let alb = eolfo-," ell/, -w * * en/fn = c / d ; we prove the statement by induction on n. By duality, we can assume that en-l/fa-l p w c / d and by theinduction hypothesis there exist eL-i >fk-i, such that e ~ - i l f ~ - i = walb and f,-tSfi-i
<
e:&-, i ert-110.
134
111. Congruences and Ideals
Let L be modular. As in Figure 7, define d'=dvf;-, and c' =dveL-,. Then d'veL-, = (dvfk-,)vei-, = d v ( f ~ - , v e ~ - ,=rive;-, ) =c'. By modularity, d'Aek-., = (dvfk-,)Ae;-, = (since &-,
,
,
DEFINITION 8 (G. Griitzer end E. T. Schmidt [1958d]). A lattice L i s called weakly modular i f f a, b, c, d L, b
<