Defining quality of care

Defining quality of care

Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625 www.elsevier.com/locate/socscimed De®ning quality of care S.M. Campbell*, M.O. Roland, S.A. Buetow Nat...

214KB Sizes 2 Downloads 141 Views

Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

www.elsevier.com/locate/socscimed

De®ning quality of care S.M. Campbell*, M.O. Roland, S.A. Buetow National Primary Care Research and Development Centre, The University of Manchester, Williamson Building, Oxford Road, Manchester M13 9PL, UK

Abstract This paper de®nes quality of health care. We suggest that there are two principal dimensions of quality of care for individual patients; access and e€ectiveness. In essence, do users get the care they need, and is the care e€ective when they get it? Within e€ectiveness, we de®ne two key components Ð e€ectiveness of clinical care and e€ectiveness of inter-personal care. These elements are discussed in terms of the structure of the health care system, processes of care, and outcomes resulting from care. The framework relates quality of care to individual patients and we suggest that quality of care is a concept that is at its most meaningful when applied to the individual user of health care. However, care for individuals must placed in the context of providing health care for populations which introduces additional notions of equity and eciency. We show how this framework can be of practical value by applying the concepts to a set of quality indicators contained within the UK National Performance Assessment Framework and to a set of widely used indicators in the US (HEDIS). In so doing we emphasise the di€erences between US and UK measures of quality. Using a conceptual framework to describe the totality of quality of care shows which aspects of care any set of quality indicators actually includes and measures and, and which are not included. 7 2000 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. Keywords: Quality; Care; HEDIS; NHS

Introduction Growing demand for health care, rising costs, constrained resources, and evidence of variations in clinical practice have increased interest in measuring and improving the quality of health care in many countries of the world. Quality improvement is high on the national agenda both in the UK (Roland, Holden & Campbell, 1999) and in the USA (Schuster, McGlynn

* Corresponding author. Tel.: +44-0161-275-7601; fax: +44-0161-275-7600. E-mail address: [email protected] (S.M. Campbell).

& Brooks, 1998). There has been a move away from assessing costs and activity to assessing quality with an emphasis on both ecient use of resources and on the e€ectiveness of health care. In the UK this trend has led to an emphasis on both performance measurement and quality improvement for the NHS, and the development of a national performance framework (Department of Health, 1997; NHS Executive, 1999). Within this, clinical governance will form a framework through which `NHS organisations are accountable for monitoring and improving the quality of their services', with the aim of promoting `an environment where excellence of clinical care will ¯ourish' (NHS Executive, 1998a,b). The increasing focus by governments on improving

0277-9536/00/$ - see front matter 7 2000 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. PII: S 0 2 7 7 - 9 5 3 6 ( 0 0 ) 0 0 0 5 7 - 5

1612

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

quality of care requires that the concept is clearly understood. In this paper we de®ne quality of care. We focus speci®cally upon care received by individuals from formal institutional health care systems which individuals or carers have chosen to access. Care in this context refers to care provided by any health care professional. We suggest that there are two dimensions of quality in this context; access and e€ectiveness. In essence, do users get the care they need, and is the care e€ective when they get it? There are two key elements of e€ectiveness Ð clinical e€ectiveness and the e€ectiveness of inter-personal care Ð and both of these should be related to need. These elements are discussed with reference to the structure of the health care system, processes of care and outcomes resulting from care. The aim of accessing e€ective health care for individuals is to maximise health bene®t according to need. We suggest that quality of care is a concept that is at its most meaningful when applied to the individual user of health care. However, care for individuals must be placed within the context of providing health care for populations. We also de®ne quality of care for populations by reference to a separate but overlapping set of criteria re¯ecting the opportunity cost of providing care for any individual patient or group of patients. We show how our framework can be of practical value by applying the concepts outlined to the set of performance indicators proposed for use in the UK (NHS Executive, 1999) and a widely used set of US quality indicators, HEDIS 3.0 (National Committee for Quality Assurance, 1998). A framework is important as it both increases understanding of what such sets of indicators mean and also those aspects of care that should be covered and which are, and are not, actually being covered. Many symptoms experienced by individuals are not presented to formal health care systems (Rogers, Hassell & Nicholaas, 1999). We recognise that pathways to formal care are complex and multidimensional (Campbell & Roland, 1996; Rogers et al., 1999). They are dependent on factors which include the sociodemographic characteristics of the population (Ben-Shlomo, White & McKeigue, 1992; MacIntyre, McIver & Sooman, 1993), health need (Evandrou, Falkingham, Le Grand & Winter, 1992; Feinstein, 1993) and factors such as lay support (Robinson & Gran®eld, 1986; Oakley, 1994), frequent attendance (Neal, Heywood, Morley, Clayden & Dowell, 1998) and health beliefs (Egan & Beaton, 1987; Murray & Corney, 1990; Van der Kar, Knottnerus, Meertens, Dubois & Kog, 1992). However, this paper does not focus on the attributes of health care systems which might in¯uence consulting behaviour. Rather, we focus speci®cally upon care received by individuals from formal institutional health

care systems starting from where an individual or carer has decided to access care. We ®rst de®ne the components of care, then the attributes of quality. We bring these together to provide a framework to describe quality of care. De®ning health care De®nitions of care are varied and contested (Heyman, 1995; Webb, 1996; McCance, McKenna & Boore, 1997). For the purposes of this paper, we de®ne health care as being composed of health care systems and actions taken within them designed to improve health or well-being. Donabedian (1966, 1988) ®rst proposed a systems-based framework of structure, process and outcome. These have also been described as categories of care (Ellis & Whittington, 1993). Donabedian's model has been used previously as a basis for de®ning quality (Ste€en, 1988; Tarlov, Ware, Green®eld, Nelson, Perrin & Zubko€, 1989; Baker, 1995; Irvine & Donaldson, 1993). It is necessary to distinguish between the structure of health care, actual care given (process) and the consequences of the interaction between individuals and a health care system (outcome). We suggest that outcome is not a component of care but a consequence of care. Similarly, structure is not a component of care but the conduit through which care is delivered and received. Fig. 1 shows the key domains underlying structure, process and outcome for care received by individuals from a health care system and the dimensions of each of these domains. Structure Structure refers to the organisational factors that de®ne the health system under which care is provided (Donabedian, 1980). We identify two domains of structure: physical characteristics and sta€ characteristics, and Fig. 1 shows the dimensions of each of these domains. Components of the dimension of resources include, for example, personnel, equipment and buildings. The ways in which those services are organised would include, for example, opening hours and the existence or otherwise of a booking system for appointments. These are both structural elements of the health care system. Structural features of health care provide the opportunity for individuals to receive care but do not guarantee it. On the whole structures, whilst being able to increase or decrease the likelihood of receiving high quality care, are indirect and contingent in¯uences on care. However, structural features within a systems based model of care can have a direct impact on processes and outcomes, e.g. if necessary equipment or skills are not available

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

to undertake an e€ective examination or if all appointments are booked-up prohibiting a patient accessing care. Process Processes of care involve interactions between users and the health care structure; in essence, what is done to or with users. Process is the actual delivery and receipt of care. Two key processes of care have often been identi®ed: technical interventions and inter-personal interactions between users and members of a healthcare system (Blumenthal, 1996; Donabedian, 1988, 1992; Irvine, 1990; Tarlov et al., 1989; Ste€en, 1988). Technical care refers to the application of clinical medicine to a personal health problem (Donabedian, 1980) and is based upon a theory of function which can be evaluated for ecacy and generally standardised. Care should be appropriate and necessary (Kahan et al., 1994; Brook, 1994). In practice, care is often overused, i.e. provided when inappropriate, and underused, i.e. not provided when necessary (Brook, McGlynn & Cleary, 1996; Schuster et al., 1998). Both necessary and appropriate care must be seen from both ends of the scale; for example, appropriateness is used as much to de®ne what is inappropriate as appropriate. Both `clinical care' and `technical care' have been used to describe the more bio-medically oriented aspects of health professional's behaviour. We suggest that clinical care is the more appropriate term to use as there are also technical aspects to inter-personal care, e.g. speci®c skills in relation to giving information to patients. We therefore de®ne the process of care in terms of clinical and interpersonal aspects of care. Interpersonal care describes the interaction of health care professionals and users or their carers. This includes ``the management of the social and psycho-

1613

logical interaction between client and practitioner'' (Donabedian, 1980). A number of skills underlie good inter-personal skills including: communication, the ability to build a relationship of trust, understanding and empathy with the patient (Blumenthal, 1996) and to show humanism, sensitivity and responsiveness (Carmel & Glick, 1996). Patients want explanation and discussion about their symptoms (Woloshynowych, Valori & Salmon, 1998), and to be involved in decisions about their management. Both clinical and inter-personal care processes involve the de®nition and communication of problems or needs, diagnoses, their management and co-ordination by the patient and professional concerned. In addition to actions taken by an health professional, identi®ed as elements of process in Fig. 1, the process of care may be further classi®ed into preventive care, care for chronic disorders, and care for acute illness. This classi®cation is particularly relevant to quality measurement, since quality indicators abound for the ®rst, are patchy for the second, and almost absent for the third. The lack of quality indicators for acute minor illness has important implications for assessing the quality of general/family practice where they form the bulk of all presenting problems. Clinical and interpersonal aspects of care are relevant for each consultation and apply equally to chronic, acute or preventive care. Outcome Outcomes are consequences of care. Structure as well as processes may in¯uence outcome, indirectly or directly. For example, a patient may die from cervical cancer either because a screening service is not available (structure) or because her cytology report is misread (process). However, the relative importance of each of these components will vary in di€erent situations and the relationships between them are not necessarily linear.

Fig. 1. A systems based model for assessing care.

1614

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

The e€ectiveness of structure and processes (both clinical and inter-personal) can be de®ned in terms of their capacity to result in two principal domains of outcome: health status and user evaluation Ð incorporating non-health as well as health related outcomes. There may be feedback loops with, for example, an individual's user evaluation (outcome) in¯uencing their subsequent consulting behaviour, or care negotiated in one consultation a€ecting subsequent decisions (Rogers et al., 1999). Our framework focuses upon care for individual users so outcome in Fig. 1 refers to health status and user evaluation, e.g. satisfaction, enablement (Howie, Heaney & Maxwell, 1996) and health related quality of life. These must also be related to patient expectations and to the needs of that individual patient (Stott et al., 1997). User evaluation may include assessment of outcome (symptom resolution) and/or processes of care (e.g. communication skills of the health professional). Although outcomes may be explicitly related to process for both health status (e.g. Antiplatelet Trialists' Collaboration, 1994) and user evaluation (e.g. Schmittdiel, Selby, Grumbach & Quesenberry, 1997), this is not always the case (Long & Fair®eld, 1996). This is because outcomes are often causal rather than logical consequences of processes and their activation is contingent upon a wide variety of factors. Outcome C will not always follow logically from process B using structure A. Care processes may have little or no consequence on disease outcomes if, for example, an illness has an immutable natural history. There has been considerable debate about whether process or outcome should be assessed as measures of quality of care (Davies & Crombie, 1995; Brook, McGlynn & Cleary, 1996). In general, process measures are better indicators of quality of care if the purpose of measurement is to in¯uence the behaviour of the health care system: processes are common, under the control of health professionals, and may more rapidly be altered. Outcomes are often rare, may follow a change in process by up to 10 years (e.g. management of hypertension), and may be dependent on factors outside the control of the individual health professional (Giu€rida, Gravelle & Roland, 1999). However, process measures suitable for measuring quality should be clearly linked to evidence of improved outcomes. We have de®ned care as a systems based model composed of health structures and two processes of care (clinical and inter-personal) which result in consequent outcomes. However, whilst systems and processes increase or decrease the likelihood of individuals receiving the care they need, they do not guarantee quality care. We now consider the concept of quality.

De®ning quality Quality has been de®ned in a number of di€erent ways (Crosby, 1979; Donabedian, 1980; Maxwell, 1984; Peters, 1987; Juran, 1988). De®nitions of quality are either generic or disaggregated Ð approaches which are not inherently incompatible but can be seen as opposite ends of a continuum. Generic de®nitions of quality include excellence (RCGP, 1994), expectations or goals which have been met (Ellis & Whittingham, 1993; Ste€en, 1988), `zero defects' (Crosby, 1979) or ®tness for use (Juran, 1988). Other generic de®nitions are more complex. For example, the Institute of Medicine (Lohr, 1992) has de®ned quality as the `degree to which health services for individuals and populations increase the likelihood of desired health outcomes and are consistent with current professional knowledge'. Generic de®nitions are not easily operationalisable and trade both sensitivity and speci®city for generalisability. Disaggregated approaches, on the other hand, recognise that quality is complex and multidimensional (Donabedian, 1980; Maxwell, 1984; HSRG, 1992; Wine®eld, Murrell & Cli€ord, 1995). They de®ne quality according to individual dimensions or components. Some examples of previous de®nitions of quality of care using disaggregated approaches are included in Fig. 2. Each individual component of quality provides a partial picture of quality when viewed on its own, but o€er more speci®city in de®ning quality when viewed in combination. However, we propose that there are only two domains of quality Ð access and e€ectiveness. For individual patients, all dimensions of quality suggested previously, including those listed in Fig. 2, can be subsumed by and appropriately regarded, as elements of access and e€ectiveness. Quality of care may, in this way be reduced to two questions. First, can an individual get the care they need when they need it? Second, when they get the care, is it e€ective both in terms of clinical e€ectiveness and inter-personal relationships? We now develop this proposition by applying access and e€ectiveness to the systems based model of care (structure, process and outcome) described above.

De®ning quality of care for individual patients We propose a combined generic and disaggregated approach to de®ning quality of care. Our de®nition of quality of care for individuals is: whether individuals can access the health structures and processes of care which they need and whether the care received is e€ective.

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

1615

Fig. 2. Examples of previously described dimensions of quality of care.

Fig. 3 shows how access and e€ectiveness can be related to health care structures, to processes of care, and outcomes, to produce a taxonomy of quality of care for individual patients. We now develop this argument by considering separately access and e€ectiveness. Access The ®rst part of our de®nition of quality of care emphasises ``whether individuals can access health structures and processes of care which they need''. The most basic dimension of access to a health structure is geographic/physical access (Haynes, 1991). This may relate to geographic barriers to getting to health care facilities such as rurality (Watt, Franks & Sheldon, 1993; Cox, 1994), or use of premises themselves such as access by disabled or elderly people (Bentham & Haynes, 1985). Availability is the extent to which the health care system provides facilities (structures) and services (process) which meet the needs of individuals. Examples include access to a female general practitioner, a specialist clinic, or a member of a health

care team other than a doctor (e.g. nurse practitioner, physiotherapist or counsellor). The latter is increasingly important given the emergence of a far more diverse range of skills among health care providers as part of attempts to increase the cost±e€ectiveness of care (Pritchard & Pritchard, 1994). Organisational access is a sub-component of availability. If people are physically able to access a health facility, they may still face barriers to accessing care in terms, for example, of the length and availability of appointments, or whether the health professional can speak their language. In a system where the primary care practitioner acts as a gatekeeper, access to secondary care or other members of the PHCT is determined by access to the primary care practitioner and by his or her referral behaviour. We suggest that three of the four attributes of quality identi®ed as being of particular relevance to primary care (Star®eld, 1994) are sub-components of access. First contact, comprehensiveness Ð a range of services and care broad enough to meet all common needs as they occur Ð and provider continuity or longitudinality are all sub-components of the structural

Fig. 3. Dimensions of quality of care for individual patients (dimensions of quality of care for populations are considered separately in the text).

1616

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

aspects of availability, rather than quality attributes in their own right. Our view is that continuity of care is not a unique dimension of quality but a structural characteristic that may produce bene®ts, though is not guaranteed to do so (Freeman & Hjortdahl, 1997). For example, continuity of care from an ine€ective professional with poor communication skills does not constitute high quality care, even though such a professional could nevertheless score well on access and patient evaluation dimensions. In this paper, we do not include equity as a component of quality of care for individuals as equity requires a element of comparison of individuals within a population; however, we do regard equity as a key element of quality of care at the population level, which we discuss later. Monetary costs of access at the individual level are only relevant to the payer. This may be the patient where services are not free at the point of delivery. So a€ordability is a key component of access in countries where health care is not provided by the state. Financial barriers may also be important in other systems, either in terms of the material cost of attending an appointment (transport costs, childcare, prescription charges) or the opportunity cost incurred, for example, in loss of earnings. Other barriers include having to accommodate competing social role commitments into the daily routine which may prevent, for example, mothers with young children accessing health care on their own behalf (Young, 1996). Health status and user evaluation are the principal outcomes of quality of care for individuals relating to access (Fig. 3). User attitudes cannot be separated from nor properly understood without reference to the experiences with which they are connected (Cornwell, 1984). These evaluations may in¯uence future decisions about accessing care; e.g. an individual may feel disinclined to consult if the last time they consulted they were treated unsympathetically (Murray & Corney, 1990). User evaluation thus forms part of a feed back loop with acceptability a dimension of outcome within user evaluation which may in¯uence whether an individual seeks to access formal care in the future. E€ectiveness The second part of our de®nition of quality of care relates to whether, when accessed, the care received by an individual is e€ective. E€ectiveness is the extent to which care delivers its intended outcome or results in a desired process, in response to need. Fig. 3 shows the two key elements of e€ectiveness Ð clinical care and inter-personal care. The e€ectiveness of clinical care depends on the e€ective application of knowledge based care. Knowledge-based care refers to both evidence-based medicine

(Sackett, Rosenberg, Gray, Haynes & Richardson, 1996) and care which is regarded as legitimate (Donabedian, 1990). The latter relates to aspects of care that may be widely accepted without necessarily having scienti®c evidence of e€ectiveness. Knowledge-based care incorporates the extent to which a treatment or service is consistent with patients' reasonable expectations and contemporary professional standards of care, re¯ecting both societal and professional norms. For example, primary care counselling has been found to be popular with patients (Priest, Vize, Roberts & Tylee, 1996; Scott & Freeman, 1992) and is widely implemented within primary care in the UK (Sibbald, Addlington-Hall, Brenneman & Freeling, 1993) but as yet there is limited evidence for its e€ectiveness (Roth & Fonagy, 1996). Care is only described as evidencebased when there is good scienti®c evidence of a link between process and outcome; for example, the role of aspirin in secondary prevention of coronary heart disease (Antiplatelet Trialists Collaboration, 1994). Once again, processes and outcomes are context speci®c for each individual person because quality of care for individual users requires that individual circumstances and the complexity of individual patients must be considered. E€ective care, therefore, requires appreciation of the patient's personal experience of illness (Stewart, Brown, Weston, McWhinney, McWilliam & Freeman, 1995) and must align the agendas of the professional and the patient (Tuckett, Boulton, Olson & Williams, 1985). Care should be planned for and with individual patients (HSRG, 1992, p. 2154; Stewart et al., 1995) through negotiation between doctor and patient (Buetow, 1999) and shared responsibility for care (McGlynn, 1997). Focusing on the e€ectiveness of patient centred processes reduces the risk of over-emphasising scienti®c/technical aspects of care at the expense of the experiences of the individual patient. Originating in the psychodynamic study of professional patient interactions (Balint, 1964), patient centredness is increasingly regarded as a set of skills which can be taught (Stewart et al., 1995) and which are related to improved outcome (Howie, Hopton, Heaney & Porter, 1992). Patient-centredness is concerned with the meaning of care for individuals (Stewart et al., 1995; HSRG, 1992) rather than care which is generalisable to all. Co-ordination or integration of care for individual patients is also an important attribute of quality (i.e. e€ectiveness) of care, and is a further attribute of particular relevance to primary care (Star®eld, 1994). We suggest that co-ordination is a sub-component of both clinical e€ectiveness and the e€ectiveness of inter-personal skills. Co-ordination refers to the e€ectiveness with which health professionals deal with those other organisations, or other professionals within the same organisation, which impact directly or indirectly upon

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

the health or health related quality of life of the patient (e.g. social care, education or housing). We suggest that e€ectiveness, when related to individual patients, should refer to maximising care and desired processes and outcomes based upon need. We consider ecacy (Donabedian, 1990; O'Leary & O'Leary, 1992) to be a redundant component of quality of care because we are unable to conceptualise high quality care which involves delivering treatments which are ecacious (in ideal settings), but ine€ective in routine healthcare settings. We also reject acceptability as a basic component of quality or as an attribute of care: it is more appropriately regarded as an outcome or consequence of care: it is a component of users' evaluation. Stakeholder perspectives of quality of care Much has been written about the fact that di€erent stakeholders (e.g. users, professionals and payers) de®ne and perceive quality of care di€erently (McGlynn, 1997; Annandale & Hunt, 1998; Ovretveit, 1992; Joss & Kogan, 1995; Blumenthal, 1996; RCGP, 1994). The contingent nature of quality means that there will be di€erent perspectives upon the dimensions of access and e€ectiveness and on what constitutes a desired process or outcome. For example, eciency and cost± e€ectiveness are principally concerns of managers (re¯ecting a more societal perspective) whereas users emphasise patient-centredness in response to their (individual) needs, e.g. humaneness, kindness, communication and access (Wensing, Grol & Smits, 1994). Di€erences between users and health professionals (Van der Waal, Casparie & Lako, 1996), for example when an evidence-based intervention designed to produce a outcome is not wanted by the patient (Mulley, 1995), will provide examples of the e€ectiveness of the patient-centredness of care. For some stakeholders, e.g. a national healthcare system, it is the outcome for a population which is of greatest importance, rather than the outcome for individuals. We now discuss how quality of healthcare may be de®ned for populations, since this di€ers in some important respects from quality of healthcare for individuals. De®ning quality of care for populations We have suggested that quality of care has most meaning when applied to the level of the individual user of health care. After all, it is individuals who are the recipients of care. Questions about quality of care for individuals cannot be answered by reference to populations, only put in to the context of a social construction of quality of care. Borrowing from economics

1617

we recognise that care is not given as part of a closed model ceteris paribus. For example, most economic evaluations of health care adopt a societal perspective and focus on the optimisation of health bene®t for populations (Craig & Sutton, 2000). Whilst quality of care for individual patients may therefore be understood with reference to the framework outlined in Fig. 3, it also needs to be understood in terms of, and may be contingent upon, care for populations. Care for whole populations may potentially con¯ict with care for individual patients, for example, because of prioritisation of resources towards particular health needs. We have argued that consideration of quality of care for an individual requires information which is context speci®c to that user. However, a societal perspective requires information about all potential users of health care (Birch & Gafni, 1992) and this requires consideration of opportunity costs. What is done to an individual user of health care (in terms of resources, including time as well as costs) may, therefore, be contingent upon what is done to all other users of the health care; particularly within systems with resource constraints. This divergence re¯ects Donabedian's distinction between individual and social quality (Donabedian, Wheeler & Wyszewianski, 1982), with the former based upon the individual and the latter emphasising aggregate net bene®t (or net utility) for the entire population (Donabedian, 1980). At the population level we propose that there are three additional key factors: equity, eciency and cost which contribute to our model of quality of care for populations. We therefore de®ne quality of care for populations as: the ability to access e€ective care on an ecient and equitable basis for the optimisation of health bene®t/well-being for the whole population.

Access Quality of care can only be understood within the overall context in which health care is provided. Local or national factors help de®ne the context in which health care is provided in organisations Ð and these are often outside the control of health professionals (Heath, 1995; Goldstein & Speigelhalter, 1996). Examples of such factors include the availability of primary and secondary health care services, such as community psychiatric services and the availability of social services or local authority services. Theses are dimensions of structural availability at a societal level. Supply factors have been found to be important determinants of utilisation (Evandrou et al., 1992). In our framework, we de®ne equity as a sub-component of access relevant to structure and process; it is

1618

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

de®ned as the extent to which all individuals in a population access the care they need. De®nitions of access must emphasise a notion of access according to need and the timely use of services (Evandrou et al., 1992; Maxwell, 1992; Field & Lohr, 1992; IOM, 1993); both in terms of horizontal equity (equally accessible to e€ective care for all users), and vertical equity (greater access to e€ective care for those with more need). The test of equity are systematic di€erences in use and outcomes (IOM, 1993). We support Maxwell's (1992) concept of relevance as whether `the overall pattern and balance of services (is) the best that could be achieved, taking into account the needs and wants of the population as a whole' but suggest it is a sub-component of availability. In essence, services should be available on an equitable basis according to need. As with care for individual patients, health status and user evaluation are key outcomes of access for populations, in addition to equity. However, equitable access does not automatically translate into equitable e€ectiveness. E€ectiveness Within the domain of e€ectiveness, we again de®ne equity as an important component of quality of care for populations. In addition, we de®ne eciency as an attribute of quality of care for populations. Eciency is to the ratio between bene®t and costs. In essence, the most ecient use of care to maximise outcome, which can involve allocative eciency (focusing on procedures which produce maximum bene®t) and technical eciency (employing procedures in the most technically competent manner). De®nitions of eciency which are output-speci®c concentrate upon maximising desired outcomes for individual users (Ryan & Shakley, 1995). However, achieving maximum desired outcomes for all individual users may not be sustainable or a€ordable at the population level. We recognise the importance of cost±e€ectiveness when referring to health care for populations where choices have to be made between di€ering priorities for the allocation of scarce resources. At the population level, inputs are as important as outputs and resources should be distributed eciently to where there is the most potential for health gain (Blaxter, 1996). It is up to society to choose whether resources should be allocated to particular sub groups within a population (Donabedian et al., 1982) based, for example, on decisions about need and equity (Bevan, 1998). There is a need to balance e€ectiveness and eciency to gain the highest net bene®t to individuals and society (Donabedian, 1980). Eciency and quality are not mutually exclusive Ð the challenge is to fuse economic and clinical incentives (Brook, 1997). However, whether related to either individuals or populations, the ratio of cost to bene®t (process or outcome

bene®t) will increase when care is ine€ective. Ine€ective care is inecient (Ovretveit, 1992; Crosby, 1979). A€ordability at societal level is a sub-component of availability and relates for example to the rationing or prioritising of treatment. At population level the ecient use of care for the maximum desired outcomes (health status and user evaluation) within costs is paramount. This is, in essence, a `welfarist' approach to health care with an emphasis upon the sum of (health) bene®t received by each individual in society (Ryan & Shackley, 1995). However, ecient care must be provided on an equitable basis. We suggest, therefore, that at the societal level there are four outcomes of e€ectiveness; user evaluation and health status and, in addition, cost and equity. Practical application of the framework In this section, we demonstrate the utility of the framework by applying it to two sets quality indicators, the NHS National Performance Framework in the UK, and the HEDIS set developed for the assessment of health plans in the United States by the National Committee for Quality Assurance (NCQA, 1998). We show how the framework can be used to demonstrate what aspects of care are being measured and what are not, and we also show how it can be used as a framework to permit critical analysis of quality indicators. The UK government has recently published a National Performance Assessment for the National Health Service (National Health Service Executive, 1999). This framework is intended to be applied at health authority level (populations 200,000±500,000). The HEDIS set of measures provides a common dataset to enable purchasers and consumers of health care to choose between health plans (NCQA, 1998). Annual reporting of HEDIS measures us required of health plans for accreditation by the NCQA. At present there are over 100 indicators, with many more being developed, particularly in the area of clinical e€ectiveness. The indicators in the two sets are summarised in Table 1. In some cases, the distinction between access and e€ectiveness is arti®cial. For example, in the UK indicators, teenage pregnancy rate is speci®cally advanced both as an indicator of availability of services and of the e€ectiveness of those services. The following critique is not intended to be comprehensive, but rather to demonstrate how a conceptual framework can be used critically to examine measures of quality of care. Access and availability Inspection of Table 1 shows that neither set of indi-

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

1619

Table 1 HEDIS and the National Performance Framework compared Quality of care National Performance Framework indicators proposed Performance indicators in HEDIS 3.0, 1999 dimensions for individual for use by the National Health Service Executive (1999) dataset (NCQA, 1999) patients (from Fig. 3) Structure Geographic access

None

Physical access

None

A€ordability Availability

None % Adults registered with dentist % Children registered with dentist Size of in-patient waiting list

E€ectiveness

Process A€ordability Availability

Outpatient (within 13 weeks of referral) and inpatient (within 3 months of decision to admit) waiting times

None

Length of stay (fractured neck of femur, stroke) Day surgery rate

E€ectiveness of clinical care

% Children immunised

% Mammography in target population % Cervical screening in target population

None (though could be included in patient survey) None (though could be included in patient survey) Cost/member/month Rate of use of ambulatory health services No. of providers (primary care, mental health, obstetric and dentists) accepting new patients Co-ordination with education and social services Quali®cations of physicians No. of doctors who left in previous year Physicians' incentives to overtreat or undertreat Financial stability of health plan None % Follow up after admission for mental health problem % Dental checks in children in the last year Availability of interpreters No. of well child/well adolescent visits Length of stay (elective admissions, maternity care) Elective surgery rate Admission rates (hospital, nursing home) Outpatient utilisation rate (primary care, emergency room, outpatient surgery, mental health, chemical dependency) % Children and adolescents immunised % Smokers receiving advice % > 65 receiving in¯uenza vaccine % Mammography in target population % Cervical screening in target population % Pregnant women starting prenatal care by 13 weeks % Recommended prenatal and post-partum visits % Post MI patients receiving beta blocker % Diabetic patients with eye exam in previous year

Elective surgery rate (e.g. appropriate=CABG, hip and knee replacement, cataract replacement, inappropriate=D&C, grommet insertion) Hospital readmission rates within 28 days (emergency, Hospital readmission rates (mental health and and mental health) chemical dependency) Avoidable admission rate (ENT and urinary infection, heart failure, epilepsy, diabetes, asthma) (continued on next page)

1620

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

Table 1 (continued ) Quality of care National Performance Framework indicators proposed Performance indicators in HEDIS 3.0, 1999 dimensions for individual for use by the National Health Service Executive (1999) dataset (NCQA, 1999) patients (from Fig. 3)

E€ectiveness of interpersonal care Outcome Health status

Noti®cation rate for measles, pertussis and TB User evaluation/ experience

Costs of care

Rate of discharge to usual residence following stroke (within 56 days) and fractured neck of femur (within 28 days) Delayed discharge over age 75 Case-mix adjusted length of stay Emergency admission rate for >75 s Operation rate for recurrent hernia % Orchidopexies carried out below age 5 Psychotropic prescribing (volume of benzodiazepine prescribing) None Included in patient satisfaction survey Ð see patient evaluation below Under 16 conception rate Mortality (all cause age 15±64, 65±74, deaths from cancer, circulatory disease, suicide and accidents) 30 Day mortality post myocardial infarction and post surgery Cancer registration 5 Year survival rate (breast and cervical cancer) Infant mortality and stillbirth rate Decayed/missing/®lled teeth in 5 year olds

Episode rate for fractured femur Rate of operations cancelled for non-medical reasons Patients waiting >2 hours in A&E DNA ®rst outpatient attendance Generic prescribing rate Unit cost (mental health)

cators contains information on structural barriers to seeking care (e.g. physical or geographical access). This is potentially a serious omission, especially for some population groups such as the elderly or disabled. To some extent this is recti®ed (especially in HEDIS) by regarding utilisation as a measure of access: the UK set contains no information on primary care utilisation. However, as HEDIS is designed for the evaluation of care provided to those enrolled with health plans, it does not address a key equity issue in the US Ð a large uninsured population. E€ectiveness The greatest di€erences between the two sets of indicators are seen in the areas of clinical e€ectiveness and outcome measurement. These are large and re¯ect

% Elderly receiving functional status questionnaire

Patient satisfaction survey No. of patients who disenrolled in previous year Drug prescription costs High cost DRGs Costs per member per month

major di€erences between the two health care systems, and in particular di€erences in the information systems in the two countries. UK data on e€ectiveness relies almost entirely on population aggregated rates of procedures, e.g. admission rate for diabetes, volume of benzodiazepine prescribing. This makes the assumption that there are correct normative levels for these and (in these examples) `high is bad'. In the UK data, screening of children, women of cervical screening age and women of breast screening age are the only ones where an element of `need' is built into the denominator. While data on utilisation rates are collected in the HEDIS set, it is much more speci®c about procedures having been carried out in speci®c population groups Ð e.g. smokers advised to stop, and percentage of patients receiving beta blockers post myocardial infarction.

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

This type of indicator is also prominent among indicators being developed by NCQA, with the 1999 set (NCQA, 1999) containing cholesterol management after cardiovascular events, and details of comprehensive diabetes care. Di€erences in types of data available for quality indicators in the two countries relates largely to the system of billing in the US which has led to the development of detailed clinical databases and which are now being used to assess quality. The absence of such databases in the UK and the consequent reliance on information that is currently routinely available and which can only be collected at population level is a severe limitation of the UK indicators (Shekelle & Roland, 1998). Eight out of the ten current clinical e€ectiveness indicators in HEDIS 3.0 relate to preventive care, re¯ecting the prominence traditionally given to screening in US healthcare. However, this balance will be redressed with the inclusion of the types of new indicators outlined above: the HEDIS indicators are gradually being expanded into areas where health gain is most likely to result from a reduction in variability of performance. This emphasis is not seen in the UK indicators, in large part because of the limited nature of the data available for constructing indicators in the UK. Health outcomes However, while the HEDIS set appears replete with information on process measures of e€ectiveness, it is severely de®cient in terms of clinical outcomes: these are limited to the percentage of elderly receiving an annual functional status questionnaire. In contrast, the proposed UK set contains detailed mortality data, and some morbidity data. This re¯ects two major di€erences between the health care systems. The NHS provides universal coverage and has a very strong public health focus. So, mortality data ®gures prominently in the UK set. The focus of the HEDIS indicators is on health plan members, and not on the population. Since health plans can choose who they enrol, inclusion of health status and mortality might increase cream skimming by health plans, and could perversely lead to worse care for the population overall if health plans selectively discouraged enrolment by those who were likely to have poor health outcomes. To a limited extent, the HEDIS set tries to address the issue of cream-skimming, but only by recording the characteristics, including ethnic group, of enrolled Medicaid (welfare assisted) patients. However, although health outcomes are required to assess the magnitude of a health problem in a population, they are not necessarily good performance indicators for the behaviour of individual health care professionals unless sophisticated case mix adjustment

1621

can be made. Health outcomes are often determined by population characteristics and behaviours outside the control of individual health professionals, e.g. socio-demographic population characteristics (Giuffrida et al., 1999). They follow indirectly from individual health encounters, or may be separated from these by many years (e.g. as in the care of diabetic or hypertensive patients). They are therefore more suitable for use in the UK, where the government in concerned with the performance of the whole system, but less suitable in the US context, where year on year improvement is sought against published benchmarks. Inter-personal care One of the key important elements of quality of care which we have identi®ed is the quality of inter-personal care and communication. The authors of both UK and US sets of indicators are gradually incorporating users' experiences as a measure of the performance of the health care system. Direct assessment of interpersonal care is omitted entirely from the published NHS indicators, although the NHS started at the end of 1998 to conduct annual patient surveys, and it is planned that these will be reported at health authority level. Reports of patient experiences have recently become an signi®cant part of HEDIS with the inclusion of a mandatory standard patient survey (CAHPS) in the most recent version of HEDIS (NCQA, 1999). The HEDIS set also includes information on patients who disenrolled in the previous year, which may in part relate to de®ciencies in inter-personal aspects of care. Inclusion of this indicator re¯ects the greater ability of US patients to move between di€erent types of health care: this choice is available in the UK for primary care (though rarely exercised), but scarcely exists for secondary care within the NHS. Discussion There is no universally accepted de®nition of care, quality or quality of care. In this paper we suggest that quality of care for individual patients is de®ned by their ability to access e€ective care with the aim of maximising health bene®t in relation to need. This is not to say that other dimensions of quality identi®ed previously in Fig. 2 are not important, but that their role in delivering quality of care for individuals is dependent upon users actually getting the care they need and it being e€ective. Both access and e€ectiveness, and the structure and processes of health care, are measured by their capacity to result in desired outcomes and/or processes as negotiated by user and health professional. We have suggested that quality of care is a di€erent

1622

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

concept when considered for individual users or whole populations. At the societal level quality of care is the ability to access e€ective care on an ecient and equitable basis for the optimisation of health bene®t/wellbeing for the whole population. However, we regard quality of care to be a concept that has most meaning when related to individual users. The complexities and needs of individual patients or consultations are only discernible at the level of the individual and by focusing upon what is required for an individual in their interaction with a health care provider. People presenting to a health professional expect good individual care (Stott et al., 1997) which they will evaluate in relation to how it meets their individual needs (McGlynn, 1997). Population based measures of quality of care should, in part, be judged in terms of their ability to re¯ect the aggregation of individual encounters. However, this is not to say that people should necessarily get what they want Ð the health needs of individuals must be balanced against optimising health outcomes for society. There is a discrepancy between de®ning the various aspects of quality of care and the methods currently available for collecting the data and/or the political will, by organisations and governments, to collect data using di€erent methods. We have emphasised how di€erent stakeholders value di€erent components of quality of care. Moreover, our conceptual framework places inter-personal care equally with clinical care as a key process of quality of care. Importantly, the methods of measuring di€erent elements of de®ned care are not standardised and di€erent methods requires di€erent methodologies for measuring quality of care (Blumenthal, 1996). For example, methods for measuring patient-centredness and communication skills are more time consuming and expensive than computer searches of hospital clinical databases to determine admission rates. Strict reliance on explicitly measuring data quantitatively contained in administrative datasets can only measure those elements of quality of care which are consistently and reliably recorded therein. It is unlikely that data collected for administrative of ®nancial purposes will meet the requirements of data to be used for quality assessment or quality assurance. Whether policy-makers give equal weight to other perspectives and methods is a political rather than conceptual issue. The potential expenditure on comprehensive quality assessment is very considerable, and choices will need to be made between spending money on quality assessment or on direct patient care. The assessment of quality on its own is not sucient: it needs to be linked to e€ective (and cost e€ective) methods of improving quality. Moreover, if quality indicators are developed as quantitative statistical measures (as with NPF and HEDIS) it is important to consider statistical and prac-

tical issues. These include the reliability and validity of the data collected, the feasibility (ease and cost) of collecting the data and di€erences in availability and comparability of data between and within countries. We have not considered how the various components of quality of care might be weighted or compared with one another. We have de®ned quality of care as accessing e€ective care according to need. However, is a user, who receives good access but ineffective care, receiving worse or better care compared to a user who has had diculties accessing e€ective care? Moreover, is a procedure which is rated as e€ective by a health professional, but rated poorly as an outcome by a user, good or bad care? Such questions are important for measuring, as opposed to de®ning, quality of care and whilst these highlight often potentially irreconcilable di€erences between di€erent stakeholder perspectives, they will form the test of our ability to measure patient-centred care. Ultimately a national framework must assess quality of care from perspectives important to professionals, payers and patients (McGlynn, 1997). We have applied the framework to a widely used set of indicators in the US and a set of indicators proposed for use in the UK. Both the UK National Performance Framework and HEDIS attempt to move beyond simple activity measures to include indicators based on evidence and user evaluations. However, most of the indicators rely solely upon readily collectable data and on standardised population measures. Whilst this is perhaps inevitable, there is a risk that they will perversely reduce quality for other elements of care, e.g. those which have wide professional and public legitimacy (though limited evidence of e€ectiveness), and inter-personal aspects of care. There are dangers that by de®ning explicitly what is to be measured, this encourages health care organisations/ professionals to ``jump through the hoop'', safe in the knowledge that it is only performance in these aspects of care that will be measured. Moreover, inevitably, discussion of quality of care and cost often go handin-hand on both sides of the Atlantic. In the UK others have emphasised how quality of care forms part of a wider UK government strategy to manage public services (Hoggett, 1996; Traynor, 1996) driven by a desire to get ``more for less'' (Hood, 1991). In the USA there is a growing movement to ensure that the new organisational structures for measuring quality do not sacri®ce quality at the expense of costs (Schuster et al., 1998). Importantly, quality of care is both an end in itself, but can also be used as a means of addressing other agenda (e.g. control of health care expenditure). Any discussion of quality of health care must be set within the context that health care does not operate in a political vacuum. We believe that both sets of indicators are to be wel-

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

comed as important advances in measuring quality of care; in what is essentially a new and very rapidly expanding discipline. The HEDIS set is getting more comprehensive with every edition and the NHS set is the ®rst of its kind in the UK. The challenge for the future is to focus on all the important aspects of quality of care (using the most valid methodology possible and whether data are readily available using existing systems at present or not) whilst trying to minimise perverse incentives. Both sets incorporate a range of elements of quality of care and, in so doing, also emphasise that quality of care can not, and should not, be measured by one global indicator. Our models explicitly acknowledge the potential con¯icts between focusing upon individuals or populations. Providing a framework which de®nes quality in relation to care allows some of the strengths and weaknesses of any set of quality indicators to be assessed. It exposes those areas of quality of care infrequently addressed, e.g. acute care, co-ordination between professional groups looking after an individual patient and inter-personal aspects of care, and also access for `hard to reach groups'. Enthusiasm for any individual set of indicators needs to be tempered with understanding about what care is not being measured (and subsequently potentially improved). The framework outlined in this paper o€ers a basis for such analysis.

Acknowledgements The authors would like to thank Peter Bower, Toby Gosden and Ruth Young for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

References Annandale, E., & Hunt, K. (1998). Accounts of disagreements with doctors. Soc. Sci. Med., 46, 119±129. Antiplatelet Trialists' Collaboration (1994). Collaborative overview of randomised trials of antiplatelet therapy. 1: Prevention of death, myocardial infarction, and stroke by prolonged antiplatelet therapy in various categories of patients. Br. Med. J., 308, 81±106. Baker, R. (1995). Practice assessment and quality of care. RCGP Occasional Paper 29, RCGP. Balint, M. (1964). The doctor, his patient, and the illness. London: Pitman. Ben-Shlomo, Y., White, I., & McKeigue, P. M. (1992). Prediction of general practice workload from census based social deprivation scores. J. Epid. Community Hlth, 46, 532±536. Bentham, C. G., & Haynes, R. M. (1985). Health, personal mobility, and the use of health services in rural Norfolk. J. Rural Studies, 1, 231±239.

1623

Bevan, G. (1998). Taking equity seriously: a dilemma for government from allocating resources to primary care groups. Br. Med. J., 316, 39±43. Birch, S., & Gafni, A. (1992). Cost-e€ectiveness/utility analyses. Do current decision rules lead us to where we want to be? J. Hlth Econ., 11, 279±296. Blaxter, M. (1996). The signi®cance of socio-economic factors in health for medical care and the National Health Service. In D. Blane, E. Brunner, & R. Wilkinson, Health and social reorganisation: Towards a health policy for the 21st century (pp. 33±41). London: Routledge. Blumenthal, D. (1996). Quality of care Ð what is it? N. Engl. J. Med., 335, 891±894. Brook, R. H. (1994). The RAND/UCLA Appropriateness Method. In K. A. McCormick, S. R. Moore, & R. A. Siegel, Methodology perspectives (pp. 59±70). Rockville, MD: AHCPR. Brook, R. H. (1997). Managed care is not the problem, quality is. JAMA, 278, 1612±1614. Brook, R. H., McGlynn, E. A., & Cleary, P. D. (1996). Measuring quality of care. N. Engl. J. Med., 335, 966± 970. Buetow, S. A. (1999). Four strategies for negotiated care. J. R. Soc. Med., 9, 199±201. Campbell, S. M., & Roland, M. O. (1996). Why do people consult the doctor? Factors in¯uencing demand for primary medical care. Family Pract., 13, 75±83. Carmel, S., & Glick, S. M. (1996). Compassionate±emphatic physicians: personality traits and social±organisational factors that enhance or inhibit this behaviour pattern. Soc. Sci. Med., 43, 1253±1261. Cornwell, J. (1984). Hard-earned lives. Accounts of health and illness from East London. London: Tavistock. Cox, J. (1994). Rural general practice. Br. J. Gen. Pract., 44, 388. Craig, N., & Sutton, M. (2000). Opportunity costs on trial: New options for encouraging implementation of results from economic evaluations. In A. Haines, & A. Donald, Getting research ®ndings into practice (pp. 130±148). London: BMJ Publishing. Crosby, P. B. (1979). Quality is free Ð The art of making quality certain. New York: McGraw Hill. Davies, H. T. O., & Crombie, I. K. (1995). Assessing the quality of care. Br. Med. J., 311, 766. Department of Health. (1997). The new NHS: modern, dependable. Cm 3807. Stationary Oce, London. Available on: http://www.ocial-documents.co.uk/document/doh/newnhs/newnhs.htm. Donabedian, A. (1966). Evaluating the quality of medical care. Milbank Q., 44, 166±203. Donabedian, A. (1980). Explorations in quality assessment and monitoring. Volume 1: The de®nition of quality and approaches to its assessment. Ann Arbor, MI: Health Administration Press. Donabedian, A. (1988). The quality of care: How can it be assessed? JAMA, 260, 1743±1748. Donabedian, A. (1990). The seven pillars of quality. Arch. Pathol. Lab. Med., 114, 1115±1118. Donabedian, A. (1992). Quality assurance in health care: a consumers' role. Qual. Hlth Care, 1, 247±251.

1624

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625

Donabedian, A., Wheeler, J. R. C., & Wyszewianski, L. (1982). Quality, cost, and health: An integrative model. Med. Care, 20, 975±992. Egan, K. J., & Beaton, R. (1987). Response to symptoms in healthy, low utilizers of the health care system. J. Psychosom. Res., 31, 11±21. Ellis, R., & Whittington, D. (1993). Quality assurance in health care Ð A handbook. London: Arnold. Evandrou, M., Falkingham, J., Le Grand, J., & Winter, D. (1992). Equity in health and social care. J. Soc. Pol., 21, 489±523. Feinstein, J. S. (1993). The relationship between socio-economic status and health: A review of the literature. Milbank Q., 71, 279±323. Field, M. J., & Lohr, K. N. (1992). Committee on clinical practice guidelines: Guidelines for clinical practice: from development to use. Washington, DC: Institute of Medicine. Freeman, G., & Hjortdahl, P. (1997). What future for continuity of care in general practice? Br. Med. J., 314, 1870± 1873. Giu€rida, A., Gravelle, H., & Roland, M. (1999). Measuring quality with routine data: avoiding confusion between performance indicators and health outcomes. Br. Med. J., 319, 94±98. Goldstein, H., & Speigelhalter, D. J. (1996). League tables and their limitations: Statistical issues in comparisons of institutional performance. J. R. Statist. Soc. Series A, 159, 385±393. Haynes, R. (1991). Inequalities in health and health service use: evidence from the General Household Survey. Soc. Sci. Med., 33, 361±368. Health Services Research Group (1992). Quality of care: 1. What is quality and how can it be measured? Can. Med. Assoc. J., 146, 2153±2158. Heath, I. (1995). The mystery of general practice. John Fry Trust Fellowship. London: The Nueld Provincial Hospitals Trust. Heyman, B. (1995). Researching user perspectives on community health care. London: Chapman & Hall. Hoggett, P. (1996). New methods of control in the public sector. Publ. Admin., 74, 9±32. Hood, C. (1991). A public management for all seasons? Publ. Admin., 69(1), 3±19. Howie, J. G. R., Heaney, D. J., Maxwell, M. (1996). Measuring quality in general practice. Royal College of General Practitioners Occasional Paper 75, Royal College of General Practitioners, London. Howie, J. G. R., Hopton, L., Heaney, D. J., & Porter, A. M. D. (1992). Attitudes to medical care, the organisation of work, and stress among general practitioners. Br. J. Gen. Pract., 42, 181±185. Institute of Medicine (1993). Access to health care in America. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. Irvine, D. (1990). Managing for quality in general practice. London: Kings Fund Centre. Irvine, D., & Donaldson, L. (1993). Quality and standards in health care. Proc. R. Soc. Edin., 101B, 1±30. Joss, R., & Kogan, M. (1995). Advancing quality: Total quality management in the National Health Service. Buckingham: Open University Press.

Juran, J. M. (1988). Juran on planning for quality. New York: Free Press. Kahan, J. P., Bernstein, S. J., Leape, L. L., Hilborne, L. H., Park, R. E., Parker, L. et al. (1994). Measuring the necessity of medical procedures. Med. Care, 32, 357±365. Lohr, K. (1992). Medicare: a strategy for quality assurance. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. Long, A. F., & Fair®eld, G. (1996). Confusion of levels in monitoring outcomes and/or process. The Lancet, 347, 1572. Macintyre, S., McIver, S., & Sooman, A. (1993). Area, class and health: should we be focusing on class or people? J. Soc. Pol., 22, 213±234. Maxwell, R. J. (1984). Quality assessment in health. Br. Med. J., 288, 1470±1472. Maxwell, R. J. (1992). Dimensions of quality revisited: from thought to action. Qual. Hlth Care, 1, 171±177. McCance, T. V., McKenna, H. P., & Boore, R. P. (1997). Caring: dealing with a concept. Int. J. Nurs. Stud., 34, 241±248. McGlynn, E. A. (1997). Six challenges in measuring the quality of health care. Hlth A€airs, 16, 7±21. Mulley Jr, A. G. (1995). Industrial quality management science and outcomes research: responses to unwanted variation in health outcomes and decisions. In D. Blumenthal, & A. C. Scheck, Improving clinical practice: Total quality management and the physician (pp. 73±107). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Murray, J., & Corney, R. (1990). Not a medical problem: An intensive study of the attitudes and illness behaviour of low attenders with psychosocial problems. Soc. Psychiat. Psychiatr. Epid., 25, 159±164. National Committee for Quality Assurance. (HEDIS 3.0/ 1998). Volume 1. Narrative: What's in it and why it matters. Washington, DC: NCQA. National Committee for Quality Assurance. (HEDIS 1999). Reporting set measures by domain. Update available at www.ncqa.org/pages/communications/news/h99meas.htm. NHS Executive (1998a). A ®rst class service. London: Department of Health. NHS Executive (1998b). The new NHS Modern and Dependable: a national framework for assessing performance. London: Department of Health. Available on http:// www.open.gov.uk/doh/newnhs/consult.htm. NHS Executive (1999). Quality and performance in the NHS: High level performance indicators. London: Department of Health. Neal, R. D., Heywood, P. L., Morley, S., Clayden, A. D., & Dowell, A. C. (1998). Frequency of patients' consulting in general practice and workload generated by frequent attenders: comparisons between practices. Br. J. Gen. Pract., 48, 895±898. Oakley, A. (1994). Who cares for health? J. Epidemiol. Community Health, 48, 427±434. O'Leary, D. S., & O'Leary, M. R. (1992). From quality assurance to quality improvement. The Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations and Emergency Care. Emerg. Med. Clin. N. Am., 10, 477±492. Ovretveit, J. (1992). Health service quality: An introduction to quality methods for health services. Oxford: Blackwell Scienti®c.

S.M. Campbell et al. / Social Science & Medicine 51 (2000) 1611±1625 Peters, T. (1987). Thriving on chaos: Handbook for a management revolution. New York: Knopf. Priest, R., Vize, C., Roberts, M., & Tylee, A. (1996). Lay peoples' attitudes to treatment of depression: Results of opinion poll for Defeat Depression Campaign just before its launch. Br. Med. J., 313, 858±859. Pritchard, P., & Pritchard, J. (1994). Teamwork for primary and shared care: A practical workbook (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford Medical Publications. Robinson, J., & Gran®eld, A. J. (1986). The frequent consulter in primary medical care. J. Psychosom. Res., 30, 589± 600. Rogers, A., Hassell, K., & Nicholaas, G. (1999). Demanding patients? Analysing the use of primary care. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Roland, M., Holden, J., & Campbell, S. (1999). Quality assessment for general practice. Manchester: NPCRDC. Roth, A., & Fonagy, P. (1996). What works for whom? A critical review of psychotherapy research. London: Guildford. Royal College of General Practitioners (1994). In O. Samuel, J. Grant, & D. Irvine, Quality and audit in general practice: Meanings and de®nitions. London: Royal College of General Practitioners. Ryan, M., & Shakley, P. (1995). Assessing the bene®ts of health care: How far should we go? Qual. Hlth Care, 4, 207±213. Sackett, D. L., Rosenberg, W. M. C., Gray, J. A. M., Haynes, R. B., & Richardson, W. S. (1996). Evidence based medicine: what it is and what it isn't. Br. Med. J., 312, 71±72. Schmittdiel, J., Selby, J. V., Grumbach, K., & Quesenberry, C. P. (1997). Choice of a personal physician and patient satisfaction in a health maintenance organisation. JAMA, 278, 1596±1599. Schuster, M. A., McGlynn, E. A., & Brook, R. H. (1998). How good is the quality of health care in the United States? Milbank Q., 76, 517±563. Scott, A., & Freeman, C. (1992). Edinburgh primary care depression study: treatment outcome, patient satisfaction, and cost after 16 weeks. Br. Med. J., 304, 883±887. Shekelle, P., & Roland, M. (1998). Measuring quality in healthcare: what lessons can the UK learn from the US? Lancet, 352, 163±164. Sibbald, B., Addlington-Hall, J., Brenneman, D., & Freeling, P. (1993). Counsellors in English and Welsh practices: Their nature and distribution. Br. Med. J., 306, 29±33.

1625

Star®eld, B. (1994). Is primary care essential? Lancet, 344, 1129±1133. Ste€en, G. E. (1988). Quality medical care: A de®nition. JAMA, 260, 56±61. Stewart, M., Brown, J. B., Weston, W. W., McWhinney, I. R., McWilliam, C. L., & Freeman, T. R. (1995). Patient centred medicine: Transforming the clinical method. London: Sage. Stott, N., Kinnersley, P., Elwyn, G. J. et al. (1997). Measuring general practice based primary care generic outcomes. Family Pract., 14, 486±491. Tarlov, A. R., Ware, J. E., Green®eld, S., Nelson, E. C., Perrin, E., & Zubko€, M. (1989). The medical outcomes study: An application of methods for monitoring the results of medical care. JAMA, 262, 925±930. Traynor, M. A. (1996). Literary approach to managerial discourse after the NHS reforms. Sociol. Hlth Illness, 18, 315±340. Tuckett, D., Boulton, M., Olson, C., & Williams, A. (1985). Meetings between experts: An approach to sharing ideas in medical consultations. New York: Tavistock. Van der Kar, A., Knottnerus, A., Meertens, R., Dubois, V., & Kog, G. (1992). Why do patients consult the general practitioner? Determinants of their decision. Br. J. Gen. Pract., 42, 313±316. Van der Waal, M. A. E., Casparie, A. F., & Lako, C. J. (1996). Quality of care: A comparison of preferences between medical specialities and patients with chronic diseases. Soc. Sci. Med., 42, 643±649. Watt, I. S., Franks, A. J., & Sheldon, T. A. (1993). Health and health care of rural populations in the UK: Is it better or worse? J. Epid. Communit. Hlth, 48, 16±21. Webb, C. (1996). Caring, curing, coping: Towards an integrated model. J. Adv. Nurs., 23, 960±968. Wensing, M., Grol, R., & Smits, A. (1994). Quality judgements by patients on general practice care: A literature analysis. Soc. Sci. Med., 38, 45±53. Wine®eld, H. R., Murrell, T. G., & Cli€ord, J. (1995). Process and outcomes in general practice consultations: Problems in de®ning high quality care. Soc. Sci. Med., 41, 969±975. Woloshynowych, M., Valori, R., & Salmon, P. (1998). General practice patients' beliefs about their symptoms. Br. J. Gen. Pract., 48, 885±889. Young, R. (1996). The household context for womens' health care decisions: Impacts of UK policy changes. Soc. Sci. Med., 42, 949±963.