Accepted Manuscript Finite REA-groups are solvable
Cai Heng Li, Lei Wang
PII: DOI: Reference:
S0021-8693(18)30691-4 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jalgebra.2018.11.033 YJABR 16977
To appear in:
Journal of Algebra
Received date:
12 February 2018
Please cite this article in press as: C.H. Li, L. Wang, Finite REA-groups are solvable, J. Algebra (2019), https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jalgebra.2018.11.033
This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.
FINITE REA-GROUPS ARE SOLVABLE CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
Abstract. It is proved that finite REA-groups are solvable. A major step in the proof is based on an independent result about finite simple groups.
keywords. Solvable group, Simple group, REA-group 1. Introduction Two elements a, b of a group G are called fused or inverse-fused if a is conjugate under Aut(G) to b or b−1 , respectively. In the study of Cayley graph representations of complete multi-partite graphs, the concept of REA-group was introduced in [11]. Definition 1.1. A group G is called an REA-group (REA stands for relative elementary abelian), if there exists a subgroup N < G such that any two elements of G \ N are fused or inverse-fused. To emphasise this subgroup, G is sometimes said to be an REA-group relative to N . Examples of REA-groups include abelian p-groups, groups of order p3 , and lots of Frobenius groups. The main result of this paper is the following theorem. Theorem 1.2. Finite REA-groups are solvable. The proof of Theorem 1.2 is dependent on the following result about finite simple groups, which may be of independent interest. (Denote by ΔL(n, pe ) the extension of SL(n, pe ) by the automorphism φδ, where φ, δ are generators of field and diagonal automorphism of SL(n, pe ), respectively. Set PΔL(n, pe ) = ΔL(n, pe )/Z(SL(n, pe )). Theorem 1.3. Let G be an almost simple group, and let N be a proper normal subgroup in G. Then G \ N contains elements of different orders, and further either (i) G \ N contains elements of order divisible by two distinct primes, or (ii) G = PΔL(2, 32 ) for some positive integer , G/N = C2 , and an element of G \ N has order 2+1 or 2+2 . One of our principle motivations for studying REA-groups comes from studying Cayley graph representations of certain graphs. Recall that a Cayley graph Γ = Cay(G, S) is called normal edge-transitive if the normaliser NAutΓ (G) is edgetransitive on Γ . In [11], it was shown that if a complete multi-partite graph is a normal edge-transitive Cayley graph of a group G, then G is an REA-group. We thus have the following consequence. Corollary 1.4. If a complete multi-partite graph is a normal edge-transitive Cayley graph of a group G, then G is solvable. Date: December 13, 2018. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. 20B05, 20D05. 1
2
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
We remark that there is a family of groups, which have quite similar properties to / G REA-groups. A group G is called a Camina group if all elements of gG with g ∈ are conjugate to g, refer to [2, 10]. Recently, Guralnick and Navarro [7] initiated the study of groups G which have a normal subgroup N such that all elements of gN with g ∈ / N are conjugate to g, and proved that such normal subgroups N are solvable. Motivated by this result in [7] and Theorem 1.3, we would like to propose the following question. Question. Is there a non-solvable group N and an automorphism g of N such that all elements of gN have the same order? 2. A reduction In this section, we reduce Theorem 1.2 to Theorem 1.3. We first quote some properties of REA-groups, obtained in [11]. Lemma 2.1. Let G be an REA-group with respect to N . Then (i) N G, and G/N ∼ = Cdp , where p is a prime and d is a positive integer; (ii) all elements of G \ N are of the same order pe for some integer e, and no element of G \ N centralises a non-identity element of N of order coprime to p. Lemma 2.2. Let G be an REA-group relative to N , and let R be a proper characteristic subgroup of G. Then R N . Proof. Suppose for a contradiction that R N . Let g1 ∈ R\N . Then g1 ∈ G\N . If R∪N = G, then by our assumption, N < R, and so R = G, which is a contradiction. Thus R ∪ N ⊂ G. Let g2 ∈ G \ (R ∪ N ). Since G is an REA-group relative to N , there exists θ ∈ Aut(G) such that g1 θ = g2 . Since R is a characteristic subgroup 2 of G, it follows that g2 ∈ R, which is a contradiction. Thus R N . The socle of a group G is the product of all minimal normal subgroups of G. This is denoted by soc(G). The radical of G is the largest solvable normal subgroup of G, denoted by rad(G). Let G be a finite group with socle T , where T is nonabelian simple, and 1. Then Aut(G) is isomorphic to a subgroup of Aut(T ). Thus G and Aut(G) can be viewed as subgroups of Aut(T ) = Aut(T ) S , and so each element of G and Aut(G) can be written as (t1 , . . . , t )π, where ti ∈ Aut(T ) and π ∈ S .
(2.1)
Take any g ∈ G. Then, by (2.1), g = (x1 , . . . , x )π, where xi ∈ Aut(T ) and π ∈ S . Assume that π = 1. Write π = π1 · · · πs , where the πi ∈ S are pairwise disjoint cycles. Let ki+1 = o(πi+1 ) + ki with k0 = 0, where 0 i s − 1. Without loss of generality, we may assume that πi+1 = (ki + 1, ki + 2, . . . , ki+1 − 1, ki+1 ). Lemma 2.3. With the notation above, there exists h ∈ Aut(T ) such that g h = g1 · · · gs gˆπ,
REA-GROUPS
3
where gi+1 = (1, . . . , 1, ti+1 , 1, . . . , 1) for some ti+1 ∈ Aut(T ) in the (ki + 1)th coordinate for 0 i s − 1, and gˆ = (1, . . . , 1, xks +1 , . . . , x ). Proof. Set xˆi+1 = (1, . . . , 1, xki +1 , . . . , xki+1 , 1, . . . , 1)πi+1 , and gˆ = (1, . . . , 1, xks +1 , . . . , x ). π
j+1 Notice that for j = i, we have xˆi+1 = xˆi+1 . Also since gˆπi+1 = gˆ, it follows that
g = xˆ1 · · · xˆs gˆ. Let hki +1 = 1 and hki +j = xki +j xki +j+1 · · · xki+1 , where 2 j ki+1 − ki . Set ˆ i+1 = (1, . . . , 1, hk +1 , . . . , hk , 1, . . . , 1). h i i+1 A straightforward calculation shows ˆ h
i+1 −1 xˆi+1 = (1, . . . , 1, h−1 ki +1 xki +1 hki +2 , . . . , hki+1 xki+1 hki +1 , 1, . . . , 1)πi+1 = (1, . . . , 1, xki +1 · · · xki+1 , 1, . . . , 1)πi+1 .
Denote by ti+1 the element xki +1 · · · xki+1 . Let gi+1 = (1, . . . , 1, ti+1 , 1, . . . , 1), ˆ h
i+1 where ti+1 lies in the (ki + 1)th coordinate. Then xˆi+1 = gi+1 πi+1 . Set ˆ s. ˆ1 · · · h h=h ˆ πi+1 = h ˆ j+1 with j = i, Then h ∈ Aut(T ) . We first note that gˆh = gˆ. Also since h j+1
ˆ h
j+1 we have xˆi+1 = xˆi+1 . Thus
ˆ
ˆ
xh1 1 · · · xˆshs )ˆ g = (g1 π1 ) · · · (gs πs )ˆ g = g1 · · · gs gˆπ. g h = (ˆ π
i+1 The last equality follows from gj+1 = gj+1 with j = i, and gˆπi+1 = gˆ. This completes the proof of Lemma 2.3.
2
The following lemma reduces Theorem 1.2 to almost simple groups. Lemma 2.4. Assume that Theorem 1.3 holds. Then REA-groups are solvable. Proof. Suppose that G is a non-solvable REA-group relative to N . Since G/N is a p-group by Lemma 2.1, N is non-solvable. Note that rad(G) is a characteristic subgroup of G. By Lemma 2.2, we have rad(G) N . By [11, Lemma 2.2], G/rad(G) is an REA-group relative to N/rad(G). Thus, to complete the proof of the lemma, we may assume that the radical rad(G) is trivial. Then soc(G) = M1 × · · · × Mr , where the Mi are non-isomorphic nonabelian characteristically simple groups. By Lemma 2.2, soc(G) N . If r 2, then M2 × · · · × Mr is a characteristic subgroup of G. By [11, Lemma 2.2], G/(M2 × · · · × Mr ) is an REA-group relative to N/(M2 × · · · × Mr ). Thus, to complete the proof of this lemma, we may further assume that soc(G) = T = T1 × · · · × T , where Ti ∼ = T is a nonabelian simple group, and is a positive integer. Therefore, G Aut(T ) S = Aut(T ) :S . We fix an element x ∈ G \ N.
4
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
By Lemma 2.1, o(x) = pe with p prime and e 1. By (2.1), x can be written as x = (t1 , . . . , t )π, where ti ∈ Aut(Ti ) and π ∈ S . It is clear that o(π) = pf with f e. Let y = (y1 , . . . , y ) ∈ T . Then xy = (t1 , . . . , t )π(y1 , . . . , y ) = (t1 y1π , . . . , t yπ )π, belonging to G \ N because T N . Suppose first that π = 1. Then each ti is a p-element, and o(ti ) pe . Since o(x) = pe , we may assume, without loss of generality, that o(t1 ) = pe . If t1 belongs to T1 , then we may choose y1 ∈ T1 such that t1 y1 is not of p-power order, and neither is xy, which is a contradiction. Thus t1 ∈ Aut(T1 ) \ T1 . Let Tˆ1 = T1 × 1 × · · · × 1 < T1 ×· · ·×T . Let H = Tˆ1 , x and L = Tˆ1 , xp . Then LH. Since o(x) = o(t1 ) = pe , it implies that H is an almost simple group. Noting that |H:L| = p, we have (H \ L) ∩ N = ∅. By Lemma 2.1, all elements of H \ L have the same order pe , contradicting Theorem 1.3. Suppose now that π = 1. Write π = π1 · · · πs , where the πi ∈ S are pairwise disjoint cycles. Let ki = o(πi ) + ki−1 with k0 = 0, where 1 i s. Without loss of generality, we may assume that πi = (ki−1 + 1, ki−1 + 2, . . . , ki − 1, ki ). x1 · · · xˆs+1 )π with By Lemma 2.3, there exists some h ∈ Aut(T ) such that xh = (ˆ xˆi = (1, . . . , 1, xi , 1, . . . , 1), and xˆs+1 = (1, . . . , 1, tks +1 , . . . , t ), where xi ∈ Aut(T ) lies in the (ki−1 + 1)th coordinate. Noting that Gh ∼ = G and N h ∼ = N , it follows that Gh is an REA-group relative to N h . Thus, to prove the remainder of the lemma, we may replace G and N by Gh and N h , respectively. Therefore, xh ∈ G \ N , and so, for convenience, denote the element xh by x. That is to say, x has the form as x = (ˆ x1 · · · xˆs+1 )π. Since x and xy belong to G \ N , there exists α ∈ Aut(G) such that xα = xy or (xy)−1 . By (2.1), α can be written as α = (α1 , . . . , α )ρ−1 , where αi ∈ Aut(T ) and ρ−1 ∈ S . −1
−1
x1 · · · xˆs+1 )π)(α1 ,...,α )ρ = xπ ρ , where x ∈ Aut(T ) . Similarly, xy = Then xα = ((ˆ −1 x˜π and (xy)−1 = xˆπ −1 where x˜, xˆ ∈ Aut(T ) . Thus xπ ρ = xα equals xy = x˜π or −1 (xy)−1 = xˆπ −1 . It follows that π ρ = π where = 1 or −1, and so (π ρ ) = (π )ρ = −1 π, forcing π ρ = π = π . This implies that π1ρ = πi0 for some i0 . In any case, ρ induces a permutation of {{π1 , π1−1 }, . . . , {πs , πs−1 }}. Relabelling if necessary, we may assume that k = o(π1 ) = max{o(πi ) | 1 i s}. We separate the argument into two cases. To complete the rest of the proof, we may take y1 = t and yi = 1 for 2 i . Then y = (y1 , y2 , . . . , y ) = (t, 1, . . . , 1).
REA-GROUPS
5
Case 1: Assume that π1ρ = π1 . We compute x2 = (x1 , 1, . . . , 1, x1 , . . . )π 2 , and (xy)2 = (x1 , 1, . . . , 1, t, tx1 , . . . )π 2 . Furthermore, for the integer k defined above, a calculation shows that xk = (x1 , x1 , . . . , x1 , . . . ), (xy)k = (x1 t, tx1 , . . . , tx1 , . . . ) = ((tx1 )t , tx1 , . . . , tx1 , . . . ). Since o(x) = o(xy) = pe , from the above it follows that x1 and tx1 are of p-power order. If x1 belongs to T1 , then we may choose t ∈ T1 such that tx1 is not of p-power order, and so neither is (xy)k , which is a contradiction. Thus x1 ∈ Aut(T1 ) \ T1 . Now we readily check that −1
(xk )α = (x1 , . . . x1 , . . . )(α1 ,...,αk ,... )ρ = (xα1 1ρ , . . . xα1 kρ , . . . ).
Since xα = (xy) , we have (xk )α = (xy)k , and thus ((tx1 )t ) = (x1 t) = xα1 1ρ , that is, tx1 is conjugate to x1 or x−1 1 . It follows that both x1 and tx1 have the same order f p , where f is an integer. Since t is arbitrary, all elements of T1 x1 have the same order equal to pf . Case 2: Assume that π1ρ = πi0 for i0 = 1. Let m be the length of the orbit ρ {π1 , π1−1 }ρ . Relabelling if necessary, we may assume πi+1 = πi+2 (reading the subscripts modulo m), where 0 i m − 1. By our assumption, πi+1 = (ik + 1, ik + 2, . . . , (i + 1)k). Let x ˆm+1 · · · xˆs+1 , and π m+1 = x m+1 = πm+1 · · · πs . It is easily shown that π
j+1 = xˆi+1 , x xˆi+1 m+1
πj+1
π
m+1 m+1 = x ˆi+1 = xˆi+1 , y πj = y and y π = y, m+1 , x
where 0 j = i m − 1 and 1 < j m. It follows that x = (ˆ x1 π1 )(ˆ x2 π2 ) · · · (ˆ xm πm )(x m+1 π m+1 ), and x2 π2 ) · · · (ˆ xm πm )(x π xy = (ˆ x1 π1 y)(ˆ m+1 m+1 ).
(2.2)
Arguing as in Case 1, we calculate that (ˆ x1 π1 y)k = ((tx1 )t , tx1 , . . . , tx1 , 1, . . . , 1), and (ˆ xi+1 πi+1 )k = (1, . . . , 1, xi+1 , xi+1 , . . . , xi+1 , 1, . . . , 1). By (2.2), we conclude that k x1 π1 )k (ˆ x2 π2 )k · · · (ˆ xm πm )k (x xk = (ˆ m+1 π m+1 ) , and k x1 π1 y)k (ˆ x2 π2 )k · · · (ˆ xm πm )k (x (xy)k = (ˆ m+1 π m+1 ) .
It follows that xk = (x1 , . . . , x1 , . . . , xi , . . . , xi , . . . , xm , . . . , xm , . . . ), and (xy)k = (((tx1 )t ) , (tx1 ) , . . . , (tx1 ) , . . . , xi , . . . , xi , . . . , xm , . . . , xm , . . . ). By Case 1, x1 ∈ Aut(T1 ) \ T1 . Let wik+j = xi+1 , where 1 j k. Then xk = (w1 , . . . , wk , . . . , w(i−1)k+1 , . . . , wik , . . . , w(m−1)k+1 , . . . , wmk , . . . ). Noting that α = (α1 , . . . , α )ρ−1 , we have α
−1
(i+1)k+1 αmk (xk )α = (w1α1 , . . . , w(i+1)k+1 , . . . , wmk , . . . )ρ α((i+1)k)ρ α(mk)ρ = (w1αρ1ρ , . . . , w((i+1)k) ρ , . . . , w(mk)ρ , . . . ).
6
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
Since xα = (xy) , we obtain (xk )α = (xy)k . By comparing the (ik + 1)th coordinates of (xk )α and (xy)k for 0 i m − 1, we have α
α
ρ
ρ
(ik+1) ((m−1)k+1) ((tx1 )t ) = w1αρ1ρ , . . . , xi+1 = w(ik+1) ρ , . . . , xm = w((m−1)k+1)ρ .
(2.3)
ρ Recall that πi+1 = πi+2 (reading the subscripts modulo m), and πi+1 = (ik + 1, ik + 2, . . . , (i+1)k). Then (ik+1)ρ = (i+1)k+i where i ∈ {1, . . . , k}. Let θi+1 = α(ik+1)ρ where 0 i m − 1. Recall that wik+j = xi+1 where 1 j k. It is easily shown that α(ik+1)ρ α((m−1)k+1)ρ θi+1 θm w1αρ1ρ = xθ21 , . . . , w(ik+1) ρ = xi+2 , . . . , w((m−1)k+1)ρ = x1 .
By (2.3), we have θ
i+1 ((tx1 )t ) = xθ21 , . . . , xi+1 = xi+2 , . . . , xm = xθ1m .
Set θ = θm θm−1 · · · θ1 . Then θ θm−1 ···θ1
xθ1 = x1m
= (xm )θm−1 ···θ1 = · · · = (xθ21 )
m−1
m
= ((tx1 )t ) .
That is to say, tx1 and x1 are conjugate or inverse-conjugate. So tx1 and x1 have the same order equal to pf , where f is an integer. Since t is arbitrary, all elements of T1 x1 have the same order pf . Let H = T1 , x1 and L = T1 , xp1 . Then T1 L H. Since x1 ∈ Aut(T1 ) \ T1 , we have T1 < H. Noting that T1 = Inn(T1 ) by the above identification, H is almost simple. By Cases 1-2, all elements of T1 x1 have the same order pf . Let Ω = {i | gcd(i, p) = 1 and 1 i < pf }. Clearly, H \ L = ∪i∈Ω T1 xi1 . Since T1 xi1 = (T1 x1 )i , it follows that all elements of T1 xi1 have the same order pf . The same is true for H \ L. This is a contradiction. Therefore, G is solvable. This completes the proof of Lemma 2.4. 2 3. Examples in Theorem 1.3 In this section, we treat the examples appeared in part (ii) of Theorem 1.3. For a positive integer n and a prime divisor p, denote by np and np the p-part and p -part of n, respectively, namely, n = np np with gcd(p, np ) = 1. Let φ be the field automorphism of SL(2, 3e ) induced by the Frobenius automor× phism of F3e , that is, ω → ω 3 , where ω = F3e . Let δ be the diagonal automorphism ω 0 of SL(2, 3e ) induced by diag(ω, 1) = . 0 1 Lemma 3.1. Let G = ΔL(2, 3e ) with e = 2 for some positive integer , and N < G such that G/N = C2 . Then all elements of G \ N are 2-elements.
Proof. Let T = SL(2, 32 ) and σ = φδ. Then G = T :σ and N = T :σ 2 . We find that o(σ) = 2+1 . Suppose that there exists g ∈ G \ N such that o(g) is not a 2-power. Put m = o(g). Let p be an odd prime divisor of m. Set μ = g m2 and x = g m/p . Then μ ∈ G \ N and x ∈ T . Write μ = σ n t , where n is odd, and t ∈ T . Then there exist integers a, b such that na + 2+1 b = 1, and so na ≡ 1(mod 2+1 ). A calculation shows μa = σ na t = σt, where t ∈ T . Set α11 α12 a τ = μ = σt = φδt, where t = with α11 α22 − α12 α21 = 1. α21 α22
REA-GROUPS
Then
7
a
(3.4) xτ = xμ = x. Noting that τ = σt and σ ∈ G \ N , we have τ ∈ G \ N . Since p divides |T |, it follows that p | 32 + 1, p | 32 − 1, or p = 3. We divide our analysis into three cases.
i
Case 1: Suppose that p | 32 +1. Then p | 32 −1, and so p | 32 −1 for i . Thus +1 p is a primitive divisor of 32 − 1. View ΓL(2, 32 ) as a subgroup of GL(2+1 , 3). Then, by [8, p.187, Theorem 7.3], we have CG (x) CΓL(2,32 ) (x) CGL(2+1 ,3) (x) = GL(1, 32 +1
+1
).
It follows that x ∈ GL(1, 32 ) GL(2, 32 ). However, since τ ∈ / GL(2, 32 ), we conclude that τ does not centralise x, which contradicts (3.4). 1 ζ Case 2: Suppose that p = 3. By Sylow’s Theorem, we may assume x = , 0 1 . A calculation shows where ζ ∈ F× 32 1 ω −1 ζ 3 τ φδt −1 −1 φ −1 t. x = x = x = t (δ x δ)t = t 0 1 1 ω −1 ζ 3 Then tx = t, and so 0 1 1 ω −1 ζ 3 α11 α12 α11 α12 1 ζ = . 0 1 α21 α22 α21 α22 0 1 A computation shows α21 ω −1 ζ 3 = 0, α22 ω −1 ζ 3 = α11 ζ and α21 ζ = 0. −1 2 Since ζ = 0, and α11 α22 − α12 α21 = 1, it follows that α21 = 0 and ω = (α11 ζ) , and hence ω is a square in F32 , which is a contradiction.
Case 3: Suppose that p | 32 − 1. Let f be the integer such that (32 − 1)p = pf . −1 32 −1 0 ω f 0 Let ω0 = ω p . Let h = . Set H = h. Since gcd(32 − 1, 32 + 1) = 2, 0 ω0 we conclude that H is a Sylow p-subgroup of T . By Sylow’s Theorem, we may f −1 matrices, assume that x = hip , where gcd(i, p) = 1. Since xφ and δ are diagonal −3 f −1 ω1 0 ip −1 φ φt φδt τ φ we have t x t = x = x = x = x. Let ω1 = ω0 . . Then x = 0 ω13 So −1 −3 α11 α12 α11 α12 ω1 0 0 ω1 φ = x t = tx = . α21 α22 α21 α22 0 ω13 0 ω1 A calculation shows α11 ω1−1 = α11 ω1−3 , α12 ω1 = α12 ω1−3 , α21 ω1−1 = α21 ω13 and α22 ω1 = α22 ω13 . Since α11 α22 − α12 α21 = 1, there exists some αij = 0 where 1 i, j 2. It follows 2 that ω14 = 1, which is impossible. This completes the proof.
2
−1 = 2k + 1 where k 0. It is easy to see (32 − 1)2 = 2+2 . Then (32 − 1)2 = 32+2 Recall from Lemma 3.1 that σ = φδ. Let σ = σdiag(ω k , ω k ) where ω = F× . 32
8
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
Then o(σ ) = 2+1 . Set = T :σ , where T = SL(2, 32 ) with 1. G ∼ Notice that for t ∈ T , we conclude that tσ = tσ , and so G = G. Thus, for convenience, we may assume that G = G. Set τ = σ diag(ω k , ω −k ). By the previous paragraph, we conclude that 2k+1 0 ω 2 G = T :τ and N = T :τ , where τ = φ . 0 1
Let ω0 = ω 2k+1 . Set
x=
ω0−1 0 0 ω0
0 1 . −1 0
and y =
Lemma 3.2. Let H = x, y, τ . Then H is a Sylow 2-subgroup of G, and H ∩ N = x, y, τ 2 . Proof. We readily check that xy = x−1 , xτ = x3 , y τ = xy, and |H| = 22+4 . It follows that H is a Sylow 2-subgroup of G. Since N = T :τ 2 , we have H ∩N = x, y, τ 2 . 2 Set τ1 = τ m xn and τ2 = τ m xn y, where gcd(m, 2) = 1 and n 0. Lemma 3.3. Each element of G \ N has order equal to o(τ1 ) = 2+1 or o(τ2 ) = 2+3 . Proof. Let μ = diag(ω0 , 1). Then τ = σ diag(ω k , ω −k ) = φμ. We easily check 3m −1 that τ m = φm μ 2 . By Lemma 3.2, each element of H \ N has the form as n(32m −1) 32m −1 − 3m −1 2
of τ1 or τ2 . A calculation shows that τ12 = diag(ω0 (3m −2n)(32m −1) 2(3m +1)
diag(ω0
(2n+1)(32m −1) 2(3m +1)
, ω0
τ12
τ22
n(32m −1) 3m −1
, ω0
), τ22 =
), and further, n(32 m −1) 32 m −1 − 3m −1 2
= diag(ω0
(3m −2n)(32 m −1) 2(3m +1)
= diag(ω0
n(32 m −1) 3m −1
, ω0
), and
(2n+1)(32 m −1) 2(3m +1)
, ω0
).
Since m is odd, we compute (32 m − 1)2 = 2+2 , (3m − 1)2 = 2 and (3m + 1)2 = 4. Noting that o(ω) = 32 − 1, we have o(ω0 ) = 2+2 . Set n(32 m −1) 32 m −1 − 3m −1 2
x 1 = ω0
n(32 m −1) 3m −1
and x2 = ω0
.
Then x1 = 1 and x2 = −1, or x1 = −1 and x2 = 1, according to whether n is odd or o(τ12 )
+1
32 m −1 2(3m +1)
= 2, and so o(τ1 ) = 2 . Also since o(ω0 ) = 8, we not. It follows that 2 +3 have o(τ2 ) = 8, and hence o(τ2 ) = 2 . This implies that each element of H \ N has order equal to o(τ1 ) = 2+1 or o(τ2 ) = 2+3 . By Lemma 3.1, G \ N consists of 2-elements. By Sylow’s Theorem, each element of G \ N is conjugate to an element of H \ N . Thus the lemma holds. 2 Lemma 3.4. Let G = G/Z(G) and N = N/Z(G). Then G/N = C2 , and each element of G \ N has order equal to o(τ1 ) = 2+1 or 12 o(τ2 ) = 2+2 .
REA-GROUPS
9
Proof. Let τ 1 , τ 2 be the images of τ1 and τ2 in G, respectively. Since o(τ1 ) = 2+1 , / Z(G), we conclude that o(τ1 ) = o(τ 1 ) = 2+1 . A calculation shows and τ12 ∈ +2 τ22 = (τ22 )4 = diag(−1, −1) ∈ Z(G). Thus o(τ 2 ) = 12 o(τ2 ) = 2+2 . By Lemma 3.3, 2 each element of G \ N has order 2+1 or 2+2 . This completes the proof. 4. Proof of Theorem 1.3: alternating or sporadic socles In this section, one more reduction is given for the proof of Theorem 1.3. We first treat alternating groups and sporadic groups. Lemma 4.1. Let G be an almost simple group which has a socle an alternating group or a sporadic group. Let N be a proper normal subgroup of G. Then either (i) G \ N contains elements of order divisible by two distinct primes, or (ii) G = M10 ∼ = PΔL(2, 9), and N = A6 . Proof. Let T be the socle soc(G) of G. Then N T . First, let T = An with n 5. Assume G = Sn , acting naturally on {1, 2, . . . , n}. Let σ = (12), and x = (345). Then σx ∈ G \ N has order 6. If G = Sn , then T = A6 , and G = PGL(2, 9), PΓL(2, 9) or PΔL(2, 9). Suppose that G = PGL(2, 9). Then N = PSL(2, 9) ∼ = A6 . For this case, G \ N contains elements of order 10. Suppose that G = PΓL(2, 9). Then N = PSL(2, 9), PΣL(2, 9), PΔL(2, 9) or PGL(2, 9). If N is one of the first three groups, then G \ N contains elements of order 10, and if N = PGL(2, 9), then G \ N contains elements of order 6. Suppose that G = PΔL(2, 9). By the Atlas [6], N = T = A6 , and each element of G \ N has order 4 or 8. Thus the lemma holds for T = An . Next, let T be a sporadic simple group. Then Out(G) = 1 or 2, see [6]. By our assumption, Out(T ) = C2 , and so N = T is one of the following groups: M12 , M22 , Mc L, HS, Suz, J2 , J3 , Fi22 , Fi24 , HN, He, O’N. Let M be a subgroup of G. Let G = M12 .2. Then N = M12 . By the Atlas [6], we may choose M ∼ = A4 × S3 . Thus M \ (M ∩ N ) contains = S4 × S3 such that M ∩ N ∼ an element g of order 6, and so g ∈ G \ N . Thus part (i) holds for G = M12 .2. Similarly, for G = HS.2, J3 .2, O’N.2, Mc L.2, or Suz.2, we have the following table: G HS.2 J3 .2 O’N.2 Mc L.2, Suz.2 M S8 × C2 PSL(2, 17) × C2 J1 × C2 M11 × C2 M ∩N S8 PSL(2, 17) J1 M11 It follows that M \ (M ∩ N ) contains elements of order divisible by two distinct primes. The same is true for G \ N . Thus part (i) holds for the groups G in the above table. Let G = M22 .2. Then N = M22 . By the Atlas [6], we may choose M ∼ = S6 ∼ such that M ∩ N = A6 . Then G \ N contains an element of order 6. Finally, the above argument works equally well for G = Fi22 .2, Fi24 .2, J2 .2, HN.2, or He.2, which provides the following table: G Fi22 .2, Fi24 .2 J2 .2 HN.2, He.2 M S6 S5 S12 M ∩N A6 A5 A12 Therefore, G \ N contains elements of order divisible by two distinct primes.
10
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
This completes the proof of the lemma.
2
In the remainder of this paper, we complete the proof of Theorem 1.3 for almost simple groups of Lie type. This will consist of a series of lemmas. For convenience, we make the following hypothesis: Hypothesis 4.2. Let G be an almost simple group of Lie type over Fpe . Let N be a proper normal subgroup of G such that each element of G \ N has order being a power of r, where r is a prime. Remark 4.3. Under Hypothesis 4.2, no element of G \ N centralises a non-identity element of N of order coprime to r. The following lemma shows that G \ N does not contain a field automorphism. Lemma 4.4. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then G \ N does not contain any field automorphism. Proof. Let soc(G) = T . Then T N . Suppose, by way of contradiction, that G \ N contains a field automorphism σ of r-power order. Assume first that T is a Chevalley group. Let H be a subgroup of T , which is defined over Fp . By definition, σ centralises H. Since |H| is not an r-power, this is a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Assume now that T = 2 B2 (22e+1 ), 2 F4 (22e+1 ) or 2 G2 (32e+1 ), where e 1. By [3, p.234], σ centralises 2 B2 (2), 2 F4 (2) or 2 G2 (3), which is impossible by Remark 4.3. Assume finally that T = 2 A2m (p2e ), 2 A2m+1 (p2e ), 2 Dn (p2e ), 2 E6 (p2e ) or 3 D4 (p3e ), where m, e 1, and n 4. By [12, p.12], Bm (pe ) 2 A2m (p2e ), Cm+1 (pe ) 2 A2m+1 (p2e ), Bn−1 (p ) 2 Dn (p2e ), F4 (pe ) 2 E6 (p2e ) and G2 (pe ) 3 D4 (p3e ). e
For T = 2 A2m (p2e ) or 2 A2m+1 (p2e ), σ centralises either Bm (p) or Cm+1 (p). Similarly, for T = 2 Dn (p2e ), 2 E6 (p2e ) or 3 D4 (p3e ), σ centralises Bn−1 (p), F4 (p) or G2 (p). It follows that σ centralises at least one non-identity element of T of order coprime to r, which contradicts Remark 4.3. This completes the proof. 2 5. Classical groups We treat classical groups in this section. We first fix some notation. As usual, En is the n×n identity matrix, and AT is the transpose of A. We write diag(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) for the matrix A = (aij )n×n with aii = ai for all i and aij = 0 for i = j. We write antidiag(a1 , a2 , . . . , an ) for the matrix A = (aij )n×n with ai,n−i+1 = ai for all i and aij = 0 otherwise. Let G be an almost simple classical group, defined over a field Fpe . Let soc(G) = T . Following [1], we shall use δ and δ for generators of diagonal automorphism, γ and τ for generators of graph automorphism, and φ or ϕ for a generator of field automorphism of T . We abuse notation and use the same symbols to denote both their images in Out(T ) and, when they exist, specific matrices in GL(n, pe ) that induce them by conjugation. 5.1. Linear groups, unitary groups, and symplectic groups. Let Ω be a quasi-simple group, and PΩ the quotient by scalar matrices.
REA-GROUPS
11
(i) For an element g of Ω, denote by g the image of g in PΩ. (ii) For a subgroup H of Ω, denote by H the image of H in PΩ. Lemma 5.1. Let T N G, where T = PSL(n, pe ). Then either (i) G \ N contains elements of order divisible by two distinct primes, or (ii) G = PΔL(2, 32 ), G/N = C2 , and G \ N consists of elements of order 2+1 and 2+2 , where 1. Proof. Assume first that n 3. Then Out(T ) = δ:(γ×φ) ∼ = C(n,pe −1) :(C2 ×Ce ). By [1, p.34], we may choose δ to be induced by diag(ω, 1, . . . , 1), and γ the duality automorphism g → (g −1 )T of T , where ω = F× pe . Then G \ N contains an element i j i j σ of the form φ δ or φ δ γ, where i, j are integers. Set En−2 0 H= | M ∈ SL(2, p) . 0 M Then H SL(n, pe ), and hence H T . Clearly, H ∼ = SL(2, p). Let =H∼ En−2 0 0 1 α= with A = . (5.5) 0 A −1 0 Then α ∈ H. If σ = φi δ j , then σ centralises H. If σ = φi δ j γ, then σα centralises H. Since |H| is not a power of a prime, there exist h1 , h2 ∈ H such that σh1 , σαh2 ∈ G \ N have order divisible by two distinct primes. Assume now that n = 2. Suppose further that all elements of G \ N have r-power order, where r is a prime. We pick an element σ ∈ G \ N . By Lemma 4.4, we may assume σ = φa δ, where δ is induced by diag(ω, 1), and a is a non-negative integer. For this case, we have that p is an odd prime. Let o(φa ) = f . Since gcd(a, e) = e/f , we may assume a = e/f . Let ω 0 a . τ1 = φ 0 1 p2a −1
pe −1
Then we calculate that τ12 = φ2a diag(ω pa −1 , 1), and further, τ1f = diag(ω pa −1 , 1). Since o(ω) = pe − 1, we have o(τ1f ) = pa − 1 and so o(τ1 ) = f (pa − 1). Thus as σ is the image of τ1 in PΓL(2, pe ), we conclude that o(σ) = f (pa − 1), which is divisible by 2. It follows that r = 2, and hence o(σ) is a 2-power. Write f = 2 where is a non-negative integer. If = 0, then σ = δ, and so o(σ) = pe −1. Thus PGL(2, pe ) G, but PGL(2, pe ) N for σ ∈ G \ N . Take σ ∈ PGL(2, pe ) with o(σ ) = pe + 1. Then σ ∈ G \ N . Since gcd(pe − 1, pe + 1) = 2, we have pe = 3, and so e = 1, which is impossible. Thus is a positive integer. Set 0 ω 0 1 a = τ1 . τ2 = φ −1 0 −1 0 a
A straightforward calculation shows τ22 = φ2a diag(−ω p , −ω), and furthermore, a
pe −1
pe −1
τ2f = diag((−ω p ) p2a −1 , (−ω) p2a −1 ). Since o(ω) = pe − 1, we have o(τ2f ) = p2a − 1. Let τ be the image of τ2 in PΓL(2, pe ). a
pe −1
pe −1
It is easily shown that τ ∈ G \ N . Since (τ2f )p +1 = diag((−ω) pa −1 , (−ω) pa −1 ) ∈ Z(GL(2, pe )), it implies that o(τ f ) = pa + 1, and hence o(τ ) = f (pa + 1).
12
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
By the above discussion, G \ N contains two elements σ and τ , which have orders f (pa − 1) and f (pa + 1), respectively. Since gcd(pa − 1, pa + 1) = 2, we conclude that pa = 3, and so p = 3 and a = 1. Noting that a = e/f , we have e = f = 2 . Thus T = PSL(2, 32 ), N = T, σ 2 = T.C2−1 and G = PΔL(2, 32 ) = T, σ = T.C2 . By Lemma 3.4, the lemma follows. 2 Lemma 5.2. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T is not a unitary group. Proof. Suppose T = PSU(n, pe ) with n 3. Then Out(T ) = δ:φ = C(n,pe +1) :C2e , where φe = γ, and γ is the duality automorphism g → (g −1 )T of T , see [1, p.34]. Then G \ N contains an element φi δ j , where i, j are integers. Set En−2 0 | M ∈ SU(2, p) . L= 0 M Then L SU(n, pe ), and so L T . Clearly, L ∼ =L∼ = SU(2, p). By [1, p.34], we e p −1 may choose δ to be induced by diag(ω , 1, . . . , 1), where ω = F× p2e . It follows i i that δ centralises L. Thus φ = 1. If i is even, then φ centralises L. So does φi δ j , which is a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus i is odd. Let α be as in (5.5). Then α ∈ SU(n, pe ), and so α ∈ T . Thus G \ N contains an element φi δ j α. Notice that for any g ∈ L, we have g φ = g γ = g α . It follows that φα centralises L. So does 2 φi δ j α, again a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus T is not a unitary group. Lemma 5.3. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T is not a symplectic group. Proof. Suppose T = PSp(2n, pe ) with n 2. Assume that p is an odd prime. By [1, p.34], Out(T ) = δ × φ = C2 × Ce , and δ can be chosen to be induced by diag(ωEn , En ), where ω ∈ F× pe . Set (A−1 )T 0 H= | A ∈ GL(n, p) . 0 A Then H Sp(2n, pe ), and so H T . By definition, H ∼ = GL(n, p), and hence |H| is not a power of a prime. It is easily shown that G \ N has an element φi δ j which centralises H. This is a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus p = 2. By [1, p.34], Aut(T ) = T :γ ∼ = T.C2e and γ 2 = φ. Let σ = γ i ∈ G\N , where i 1. By [3, p.234], γ centralises a subgroup Sz(2) of T . So does σ, again a contradiction. Thus T is not a symplectic group. 2 5.2. Orthogonal groups. Let V be an orthogonal space over a field Fpe , where p is a prime. Let Q be a quadratic form on V , and let β be its symmetric bilinear form with the form matrix B. (a) A vector v is singular if Q(v) = 0, and non-singular otherwise. (b) A pair of vectors (u, v) is called a hyperbolic pair if Q(u) = Q(v) = 0, and β(u, v) = 1. The plane u, v is called a hyperbolic plane. Lemma 5.4. Let U be a hyperbolic plane in V . Then (i) for p = 2, there exists some u ∈ U with Q(u) = 0; (ii) for p 3, there exist two v, w ∈ U such that β(v, v) and β(w, w) are square and non-square numbers, respectively.
REA-GROUPS
13
Proof. Let (u1 , v1 ) be a hyperbolic pair in U . Then {u1 , v1 } is a basis of U . Suppose first that p = 2. Let u = u1 + v1 . Note that Q(u) = Q(u1 ) + Q(v1 ) + β(u1 , v1 ). Since u1 and v1 are singular vectors, we have Q(u) = 1, as in part (i). Suppose now that p is odd. Let F× pe = ω. Let v = u1 + v1 and w = ωu1 + v1 if 2 is a square in Fpe , and v = ωu1 + v1 and w = u1 + v1 otherwise. A straightforward calculation shows that β(v, v) and β(w, w) are square and non-square, respectively, as in part (ii). 2 Definition 5.5. Let v ∈ V be non-singular. We define the reflection rv : V → V by rv (x) = x −
β(v, x) v. Q(v)
Let U1 , U2 , U be subspaces of V . Write U1 ⊥ U2 if β(u1 , u2 ) = 0 for all u1 ∈ U1 and u2 ∈ U2 , and call U non-singular if Q(u) = 0 for u ∈ U \ {0}. By [9, Proposition 2.5.3], V = u1 , v1 ⊥ · · · ⊥ un , vn ⊥ W, where (ui , vi ) is a hyperbolic pair, and W = 0, x or x, y is non-singular. Then dim V = 2n + , where = 0, 1 or 2. In what follows, we may identify GOε (2n + , pe ) with GOε (V ), and write each element of GOε (2n + , pe ) as a matrix with respect to the ordered basis {u1 , v1 , . . . , un , vn , xˆ, yˆ}
(5.6)
where ε ∈ {o, +, −}, xˆ = x if dim W = 1 or 2, and xˆ = 0 otherwise, and yˆ = y if dim W = 2, and yˆ = 0 otherwise, unless specified otherwise. Lemma 5.6. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T is not an orthogonal group of odd dimension. Proof. Suppose T = Ω(2n + 1, pe ) with n 3. By Lemma 5.3, we may assume that p is an odd prime. By [1, p.34], Out(T ) = δ × φ = C2 × Ce . Then G \ N contains an element δ i φj , where i, j are integers. By Lemma 5.4, there exist two elements u, v ∈ u1 , v1 such that β(u, u) and β(v, v) are square and non-square in Fpe , respectively. By [9, Proposition 2.6.3], we may choose δ = ru rv , namely, δ = diag(A, E2n−1 ), where A ∈ GL(2, pe ). Set E2 0 | M ∈ Ω(2n − 1, p) . H= 0 M Then H ∼ = Ω(2n − 1, p) is a subgroup of T . It is easily shown that δ i φj centralises H. This is a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus the statement follows. 2 Lemma 5.7. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T = PΩ+ (2n, pe ) with n 5. Proof. Assume T = PΩ+ (2n, pe ) with n 5. Suppose that p = 2. By [1, p.37], Out(T ) = φ × γ = Ce × C2 . By Lemma 5.4, there exists some x in u1 , v1 with Q(x) = 0. By [9, Proposition 2.7.3], we may choose γ = rx , namely, γ = diag(A, E2n−2 ) where A ∈ GL(2, 2e ). Let E2 0 + | C ∈ Ω (2n − 2, 2) . H= 0 C
14
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
Then H ∼ = Ω+ (2n − 2, 2) is a subgroup of T . It is easily shown that G \ N contains an element γ i φj which centralises H. This is not possible by Remark 4.3. Suppose that p is an odd prime. By [1, p.34], (δ × δ ):(γ × φ) ∼ = D8 × Ce if pen ≡ 1 (mod 4), Out(T ) = otherwise. δ × γ × φ ∼ = C2 × C2e For this case, we reorder the basis of (5.6) into {u1 , . . . , un , vn , . . . , v1 }. Then B = antidiag(1, . . . , 1). In the following, we write each element of GO+ (2n, pe ) as a matrix with respect to this ordered basis. By Lemma 5.4, there exist two elements u, v in u1 , v1 such that β(u, u) and β(v, v) are respectively square and non-square in Fpe . By [1, p.35], we may choose δ to be induced by diag(ωEn , En ), γ = ru , and δ = ru rv , where ω ∈ F× pe . Notice that for i = j, ui , vi is orthogonal to uj , vj . Then, by Definition 5.5, we readily check that γ and δ have the form ⎡ ⎤ a11 0 0 a12 ⎢ 0 En−1 0 0 ⎥ ⎢ ⎥ ⎣ 0 0 En−1 0 ⎦ 0 a22 a21 0 where aij ∈ Fpe . Let B = antidiag(1, . . . , 1) ∈ GL(n − 1, p). Let M GL(n − 1, p), of index 2. Set L = diag(1, B (D−1 )T B , D, 1) | D ∈ M . It is easily shown that LT BL = B. By [9, Proposition 2.5.7], L Ω+ (2n, pe ), and so L T . By definition, φ centralises L. A calculation shows that γ, δ and δ centralise L. It follows that G \ N contains an element δ i (δ )i γ j φk which centralises L. By 2 Remark 4.3, this is a contradiction since L ∼ = M . Thus T = PΩ+ (2n, q). Lemma 5.8. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T is not an orthogonal group of minus type with even characteristic. Proof. Suppose T = Ω− (2n + 2, 2e ) where n 3. By [1, p.37], Out(T ) = ϕ ∼ = C2e . By [9, Proposition 2.8.2], we may choose ϕ to be φ followed by conjugation by E2n 0 0 J 1 ζ where φ is a field automorphism of order e, and J = with ζ ∈ F× 2e . Set 0 1 A 0 + | A ∈ Ω (2n, 2) . H= 0 E2 Then H ∼ = Ω+ (2n, 2) is a subgroup of T . It is easily shown that G \ N contains an element ϕk , which centralises H. This is impossible by Remark 4.3. Thus the lemma follows. 2 In the remainder of this section, we will deal with the case that either T = PΩ+ (8, pe ) with p prime or T = PΩ− (2n, pe ) with p an odd prime. Since their outer automorphism groups are more complicated, we use another method to treat such groups.
REA-GROUPS
15
Let g be a simple Lie algebra over the complex field. We denote by Φ and Π respectively the sets of roots and fundamental roots relative to a fixed ordering of the additive group generated by the roots. Then, as in [5], one can replace the complex field by an arbitrary finite field Fpe after choosing a Chevalley basis {ha , a ∈ Π; ea , a ∈ Φ}. Define xa (t) = exp(t ad ea ), where a ∈ Φ and t ∈ Fpe . Set T = xa (t) | a ∈ Φ, t ∈ Fpe . Chevalley shows that, with a few exceptions, T is simple, see [4] or [5]. Later, Steinberg constructed families of groups by taking fixed points of T of a product of a diagram and a field automorphism, which are also simple unless a few exceptions and also denoted generically by T . For convenience in what follows, we use P and Q to denote the additive groups generated by all the fundamental roots and all the fundamental weights of g, respectively. Lemma 5.9. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T = PΩ+ (8, pe ). Proof. Suppose T = PΩ+ (8, pe ). By [1, p.37], γ, τ × φ = S3 × Ce Out(T ) = ((δ × δ ):γ, τ ) × φ = S4 × Ce
if p = 2, otherwise.
Then G \ N contains an element η of the form δ0 γ0 φ0 , where δ0 ∈ δ, δ , γ0 ∈ γ, τ and φ0 ∈ φ. Since T ∼ = D4 (pe ), we may assume that T = D4 (pe ). By definition, γ and τ are induced by the symmetries ργ and ρτ of the Dynkin diagram D4 , respectively. Let a be a simple root such that aργ = a and aρτ = a. Set H = xa (t), x−a (t) | t ∈ Fp . By [4, Proposition 12.2.3], we have x±a (t)γ = x±aργ (t) = x±a (t) and x±a (t)τ = x±aρτ (t) = x±a (t). It follows that both τ and γ centralise H. By definition, φ centralises H. If δ0 = 1, then η centralises H. Thus δ0 = 1. By [4, p.98], δ0 is induced by some Fpe -character χ of P , that is, xs (t)δ0 = δ0−1 xs (t)δ0 = xs (χ(s)−1 t), where s is any root of D4 , and t ∈ Fpe . By [4, Lemma 11.1.3], there exists some Fpe -character ψ of Q with ψ(a) = χ−1 (a), and by [4, Theorem 7.1.1], ψ gives rise to an element h(ψ), belonging to T . Let σ = h(ψ)η. Then σ ∈ G \ N is of r-power order. For any t ∈ Fp , we easily check that xa (t)σ = xa (((χ(a)ψ(a))−1 t)φ0 ) = xa (t), x−a (t)σ = x−a (((χ(−a)−1 ψ(−a)−1 )t)φ0 ) = x−a (((χ(a)ψ(a))t)φ0 ) = x−a (t). It follows that σ centralises H. Since H ∼ = SL(2, p) or PSL(2, p), this is a contradic+ tion by Remark 4.3. Thus T = PΩ (8, q). 2 Lemma 5.10. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T is not an orthogonal group of minus type with odd characteristic.
16
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
Proof. Suppose T = PΩ− (2n, pe ) where n 4. By [1, p.37], if pen ≡ −1 (mod 4), δ:ϕ ∼ = D8 × Ce Out(T ) = δ × ϕ ∼ = C2 × C2e otherwise. Then G \ N contains an element δ i ϕj , where i, j are integers. By Lemma 4.4, we conclude that δ i = 1. Since T ∼ = 2 Dn (p2e ), we may assume that T = 2 Dn (p2e ). Let g be of type Dn with n 4. Let a be a simple root of g such that a is adjacent to three other simple roots of g. Set H = xa (t), x−a (t) | t ∈ Fp . By [4, Proposition 13.6.3], we have H T . By definition, ϕ centralises H. It is known that δ i is induced by a self-conjugate Fp2e -character χ of P . Notice that for the root a, we have χ(a) ∈ Fpe . By [4, p.313, Hartley’s Lemma], there exists a self-conjugate Fp2e -character ψ of Q such that ψ(a) = χ(a)−1 , and ψ gives rise to an element h(ψ), belonging to T . Let σ = h(ψ)δ i ϕj . Then σ ∈ G \ N . For any t ∈ Fp , we may readily check that j
xa (t)σ = xa (((ψ(a)−1 χ(a)−1 )t)ϕ ) = xa (t), j x−a (t)σ = x−a (((ψ(−a)−1 χ(−a)−1 )t)ϕ ) j = x−a (((ψ(a)χ(a))t)ϕ ) = x−a (t). It follows that σ centralises H, a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus T = PΩ− (2n, pe ). 2 6. Exceptional groups Let T G Aut(T ), where T is a nonabelian simple group. In this section, we consider the case where T is an exceptional group of Lie type. Following [1], we continue to use δ for a generator of diagonal automorphism, γ for a generator of graph automorphism, and φ or ϕ for a generator of field automorphism of T . By abuse of notation, we use the same symbols to denote their images in Out(T ). Note first that if T is one of the following groups F4 (pe )(p = 2), G2 (pe )(p = 3), 3 D4 (p3e ), E8 (pe ), 2 B2 (22e+1 ), 2 G2 (32e+1 ) and 2 F4 (22e+1 ), then the only outer automorphisms of T are field automorphisms, refer to [13]. By Lemma 4.4, each field automorphism of T of prime-power order centralizes at least one non-identity element of T of coprime order. Thus we only need to treat the case where T is another exceptional group of Lie type. Lemma 6.1. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T = 2 F4 (2) , F4 (2e ) or G2 (3e ). Proof. First, suppose T = 2 F4 (2) . For this case, G = T.C2 , N = T = 2 F4 (2) , and r = 2. By the Atlas [6], there exists a subgroup M ∼ = C13 :C12 such that M is contained in G but not in N . It follows that there exists σ ∈ G \ N of order 4 centralising an element of N of order 3. This is a contradiction. Thus T = 2 F4 (2) . Next, suppose T = F4 (2e ) or G2 (3e ) with e 1. By [4, p.225], Aut(T ) = T :γ ∼ = T.C2e and γ 2 = φ, where φ is a field automorphism of order e. In view of [3, p.234], γ fixes 2 F4 (2) or 2 G2 (3) pointwise, according to whether T = F4 (2e ) or G2 (3e ). It follows that G \ N contains an element γ i , which centralises 2 F4 (2) or 2 G2 (3). This is a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus the statement follows. 2
REA-GROUPS
17
Recall that g is a simple Lie algebra over the complex field. In this section, we assume g to be of type E6 or E7 . For convenience in what follows, we continue to use P and Q to denote the additive groups generated by all the fundamental roots and all the fundamental weights of g, respectively. Lemma 6.2. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T = E6 (pe ). Proof. Suppose T = E6 (pe ). By [13, p.172], δ:(γ × φ) = C3 :(C2 × Ce ) if 3 | pe − 1, Out(T ) = otherwise. γ × φ = C2 × Ce Then G \ N contains an element η of the form δ i γ j φk , where i, j, k are integers. Let g be of type E6 , and let ργ be a symmetry of the Dynkin diagram of g. Let a be a simple root of g such that aργ = a. Set H = xa (t), x−a (t) | t ∈ Fp . By [4, Proposition 12.2.3], we may choose γ to be induced by ργ . Then x±a (t)γ = x±aργ (t) = x±a (t) where t ∈ Fpe . It follows that γ centralises H. By definition, φ also centralises H. Therefore, δ i = 1. By [4, p.98], we know that δ i is induced by an Fpe -character χ of P . By [4, Lemma 11.1.3], there exists some Fpe -character ψ of Q such that ψ(a) = χ(a)−1 , and by [4, Theorem 7.1.1], ψ gives rise to an element h(ψ), belonging to T . Let σ = h(ψ)η. Then σ ∈ G \ N . For any t ∈ Fp , we easily check that k
xa (t)σ = xa (((ψ(a)χ(a))−1 t)φ ) = xa (t), k x−a (t)σ = x−a (((ψ(−a)χ(−a))−1 t)φ ) k = x−a (((ψ(a)χ(a))t)φ ) = x−a (t). It follows that σ centralises H, a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus T = E6 (pe ). 2 Lemma 6.3. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T = 2 E6 (p2e ). Proof. Assume T = 2 E6 (p2e ). By [13, p.173], Out(T ) = δ:φ = C(3,pe +1) :C2e . Then G \ N contains an element δ i φj , where i, j are integers. By Lemma 4.4, we conclude that δ i = 1. Let g be of type E6 . Let ργ be a symmetry of the Dynkin diagram of g. Let a and a be the non-consecutive simple roots of g such that aργ = a. It is known that δ i is induced by a self-conjugate Fp2e -character χ of P . By [4, p.313, Hartley’s Lemma], there exists a self-conjugate Fp2e -character ψ of Q such that ψ(a) = χ(a)−1 , and ψ gives rise to h(ψ), belonging to T . Let σ = h(ψ)δ i φj . Then σ ∈ G \ N . Set H = xS (t), x−S (t) | t ∈ Fp , where e e xS (t) = xa (t)xa (tp ) and x−S (t) = x−a (t)x−a (tp ). By [4, Proposition 13.6.3], H is a subgroup of T . Since aργ = a, we have χ(a) = e e χ(a)p and ψ(a) = ψ(a)p . For any t ∈ Fp , we readily check that j
e
j
xS (t)σ = xa (((ψ(a)χ(a))−1 t)φ )xa (((ψ(a)χ(a))−p t)φ ) = xS (t), e j j x−S (t)σ = x−a (((ψ(a)χ(a))t)φ )x−a (((ψ(a)χ(a))p t)φ ) = x−S (t). It follows that σ centralises H. Since H ∼ = SL(2, p) or PSL(2, p), this is a contradic2 2e tion by Remark 4.3. Thus T = E6 (p ). 2
18
CAI HENG LI AND LEI WANG
Lemma 6.4. Assume Hypothesis 4.2. Then T = E7 (pe ). Proof. Suppose T = E7 (pe ). By [13, p.177], Out(T ) = δ × φ = C(2,pe −1) × Ce . Then G \ N contains an element δ i φj , where i, j are integers. By Lemma 4.4, we conclude that δ i = 1. Let g be of type E7 . Let a be any fundamental root of g. Set H = xa (t), x−a (t) | t ∈ Fp . By definition, φ centralises H. Arguing as in Lemma 6.2, there exists some h(χ) ∈ T such that h(χ)δ i φj centralises H. Noting that h(χ)δ i φj belongs to G \ N , we obtain a contradiction by Remark 4.3. Thus 2 T = E7 (pe ). 7. Proofs of Theorems 1.2 and 1.3
Proof of Theorem 1.3: By Lemma 3.3, for G = PΔL(2, 32 ) and N is a subgroup of G of index 2, each element of G \ N has order 2+1 or 2+2 . On the other hand, if G is an almost simple group and N G such that either G = PΔL(2, 32 ) or N is not of index 2, then there exist elements of G \ N of order divisible by two distinct primes, refer to Lemma 4.1 and Lemmas 5.1-6.4. 2 The assertion of Theorem 1.2 follows from Theorem 1.3 and Lemma 2.4. References [1] J. N. Bray, D. F. Holt, C. M. Roney-Dougal, The Maximal Subgroups of the Low-Dimensional Finite Classical Groups, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013. [2] A. R. Camina, Some conditions which almost characterize Frobenius groups, Israel J. Math. 31 (1978) 153-160. [3] R. W. Carter, Simple groups and simple Lie algebras, J. London Math. Soc. 40 (1965) 193-240. [4] R. W. Carter, Simple Groups of Lie Type, Wiley, London, 1989. [5] C. Chevalley, Sur certains groupes simples, Tˆ ohoku Math. J. (2) 7 (1955) 14-66. [6] J. H. Conway, R. T. Curtis, S. P. Norton, R. A. Parker, R. A. Wilson, Atlas of Finite Groups, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1985. [7] R. M. Guralnick, G. Navarro, Squaring a conjugacy class and cosets of normal subgroups, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 144 (2016) 1939-1945. [8] B. Huppert, Endliche Gruppen I, Springer, Berlin, 1967. [9] P. B. Kleidman, M. W. Liebeck, The Subgroup Structure of the Finite Classical Groups, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990. [10] M. L. Lewis, On p-group Camina pairs, J. Group Theory. 15 (2012) 469-483. [11] C. H. Li, L. Wang, Relative elementary abelian groups, and a class of edge-transitive Cayley graphs, J. Aust. Math. Soc. 100 (2016) 241-251. [12] G. M. Seitz, Topics in the theory of algebraic groups, Group representation theory, EPFL Press, Lausanne, (2007) 355-404. [13] R. A. Wilson, The Finite Simple Groups, Springer, 2009. Department of Mathematics, South University of Science and Technology, Shenzhen, Guangdong 518055, P. R. China E-mail address:
[email protected] Department of Mathematics, Yunnan University, Kunming 650091, People’s Republic of China E-mail address:
[email protected]