Generic automorphisms of fields

Generic automorphisms of fields

ANNALS OF PURE AND APPLIED LOGIC ELSEVIER Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997) Generic 165-180 automorphisms of fields Angus Macintyre* Ma...

977KB Sizes 38 Downloads 141 Views

ANNALS OF PURE AND APPLIED LOGIC ELSEVIER

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

Generic

165-180

automorphisms

of fields

Angus Macintyre* Mathematical Received

29 January

Institute,

1996; received

24-2Y St. Giles. oxford

0x1

in revised form 28 January

3LB.

UK

1997; accepted

12 March

1997

Abstract

It is shown that the theory of fields with an automorphism has a decidable model companion. Quantifier-elimination is established in a natural language. The theory is intimately connected (via fixed fields) to Ax’s theory of pseudofinite fields, and analogues are obtained for most of Ax’s classical results. Some indication is given of the connection to nonstandard Frobenius maps. Automorphism;

Keywords: AMS’

Existentially

closed; Pseudofinite

03ClO; 03C60

C/usszjication:

0. Introduction This

paper

some

aspects

Theorem 1. (a) Any two algebraically closedfields of the same characteristic the same jirst-order sentences of the language of field theory. (b) lf @ is a sentence qf the language qf,field theory then

satisjj

of which

originated

in some

reflections

on the Lefschetz

The principle

has two parts:

: @ holds in (Z/P)“‘g}

{P E Spec(Z)

is open or closed in Spec(Z), and so contains it contains all hut jinitely many P. Moreover,

there

(respectively, Theorem

Principle,

I now recall.

are effective

of fields 1 is useful

aspects

of fixed

0 13 it contains

to this. The theory

characteristic)

infinitely

of algebraically

is decidable.

a result

over

(2) transferring

a result

over all @” to all other

Cc to all characteristic

zero cases

cases

[ 121;

[l].

* E-mail: [email protected] 0168-0072/97/$17.00 @ 1997 Published PIZ SOl68-0072(97)00020-1

closed

For all this see [7].

in two ways:

(1) transferring

many P $T

by Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved

fields

A. Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

166

A functorial

way of expressing

I be a countable algebraically

Here

1 is via the ultraproduct

index set, and D a nonprincipal

ultrafilter

construction.

Let

on I. Let Ki (i E D) be

closed fields such that for each prime p

{i : Ki has characteristic and only, pose such

Theorem

165-180

p} $ D,

is of course due to cardinality IKil<2N”. Then fl, Ki N @. The isomorphism and is noncanonical. But now there is a feature missing in Theorem 1. Supgi E Aut(Ki) for all i. Then there is a well-defined element n, (Ti of Aut(&, Ki), that for any sentence 0 in the language of fields with automorphism

n,

ci

is a D-average

of the

ci,

and

(noncanonically)

is an element

of

Aut( a=). Consider the special case when I is the set of primes, KP is of characteristic p, and aP is Frobenius, i.e. x H xp. Then the automorphism no oP of @ deserves to be written x H xp, p a nonstandard prime, and be called a nonstandard Frobenius. What is special about these maps? There are two aspects, one tedious, and one fascinating: (1) (C, no crP) is Nl-saturated, i.e. has a kind of compactness property [lo]; (2) The elementary properties of &, aP relate to Weil’s Riemann Hypothesis for curves, and beyond to the Weil Conjectures. Already from Ax’s work [l] one knows that Fix(&, oP) is severely constrained, as &, Fix(ap), i.e. n, EPp,and so must be pseudofinite, i.e. have Galois group f and be such that every absolutely irreducible curve over it has a rational point. Moreover, that is essentially all one can say about n,Fix(crP) [l]. Let 0 = n, op. One wants to know about polynomial equations in xi,. . . ,x,, a(x, ), . ..) (T(x,), a2(x*),.. .,02(x,) )... solvable in @. By the usual device of adding extra variables this comes down to understanding polynomial systems C(xi, . . . ,x,, a(x, ), . . . , a(~,)). By the methodology of Robinson’s Test [8], if one understands enough about the solvability of such systems, then one understands the elementary theory of (C, a). This in turn means that one understands the theory (or the almost-all variant) of the class (F;lg , opp).This was my original question: P , op) decidable? Does it admit a reasonable elimination Is the theory of all ([Falg theory? What can one say about the nonstandard Frobenius maps on C? In [5] I will show that the answers to the first two questions are yes, and that the third has a beautiful answer in terms of an independent notion of generic automorphism of C. In fact, I succeed in generalizing naturally every result from Ax’s classic paper PI. This paper develops the theory of generic (or existentially closed) automorphisms of fields. Its sequel [5] will deal with the much deeper problem of showing that the nonstandard Frobenius maps are existentially closed.

A. Macintyrel

I formulated

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

the main problems

in the mid-1980s

165-180

167

and made the first progress

MSRI in 1990, when I showed that the theory of fields with an automorphism model companion.

At that time I had very helpful conversations

at

has a

with Zoe Chatzidakis,

Lou van den Dries and Carol Wood, whom I heartily thank. A result of Lou, that the fixed field of an existentially forth the conjecture

closed automorphism

that the nonstandard

Frobenius

is pseudofinite,

naturally

maps are existentially

brought

closed (equiv-

alently, Robinson generic). Later, Udi Hrushovski gave a neater formulation of the axioms for generic automorphisms (Axiom H in this paper) and this has turned out to be an inspired

move. I thank Udi for showing

me this insight.

1. Difference fields, Axiom H 1.1. Basic systems For reasons unknown to me, a pair (K, o), where K is a field and rr E Aut(K), is called a d@erence jield. The class of difference fields is axiomatizable, by an V’3 sentence, in the language of ring theory extended by a symbol for the automorphism. In both the algebraic and logical study of such structures, one must study (difference) systems, the natural generalization of polynomial equations (and inequations) to take account

of rr. Bear in mind the two simple observations

(1) and (2) below:

K/=‘X#OOK~((3/?)(a~-l=O),

(1)

K t= @(xi,. . . ,xn, 4x1), . . . , ah),

a2h 1,. . , a2M>

@ K I= ~y1...~y,[~(~l,...,~,,Yl,...,y,,~(Yl),...,~(Y,)) Ay1=o(x1)A

...

Ay,=o(x,)].

C(xi,. . . , xn) is equivalent

Then

solvability

C’(Yl,.

. ., y,,,), where C’ consists of polynomial . . ., a(~,). Such C* I call basic systems.

4Yl),

1.2. Existential

of systems

(2)

to solvability

equations

of systems

over K in yi,. . . ,y,,,,

closedness

Definition 1. (K, O) is existentially closed (e.c.) if whenever C(y) is a basic system of K, and z is solvable in an extension (K’, a’) of (K, a) then C is solvable in K. General

logical theory [ 1 l] tells us

Lemma 1. Any (K, CT)extends

to an e.c. (K’,o’),

with JK’( = max(lKI,Ns).

In the category of fields, the e.c. structures are the algebraically closed fields, which have the special property that they are axiomatized by the infinite set of conditions C, (1 dn
168

A. MacintyrelAnnals

of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

In the category of fields with derivation, studied, under the name of differentially order axiomatizations,

165-180

the e.c. structures have also been extensively closed fields [9]. These too admit nice first-

see [lo].

Theorem 2. The class of e.c. d#erence jields is first-order axiomatizable. The proof will be given a little later. First, a simple lemma.

Lemma 3. If (K, cr) is e. c., K is algebraically closed. Proof. Any automorphism

of a field extends to its algebraic

closure.

0

Definition 2. Fix(o) = {X E K : a(x) =x}. Lemma 4. Let (K, o) be e. c. Then (i) Fix(o) is perfect; (ii) the absolute Galois group of Fix(a)

is f.

Proof. (i) Clear. (ii) Note that by the absolute Galois group I mean Aut(Fix(o)a’s]Fix(o)). (K,a) is e.c. I claim that for each II 32, there exists x,, in K with @(xn) =x,,

Suppose d(~,) #

x,, j < IZ. To see this, let z be a permutation of { 1,. . . , n} of order n, and let yl, be algebraically independent over K. Extend 0 (uniquely) to an automorphism

.

. , y, 6 of

via 6(yi)=yr(i). Then one of the y’s satisfies c?(y)=y, c?j(y) # y, K(YI ,...,y,) j
is exactly n. Finally,

since Aut(Fix(a)a’s/Fix(a))

Galois Theory, we get it to be f.

is procyclic

by elementary

0

Just as simple is

Lemma 5. Let (K, CJ) be e. c., and let f (x, y) = 0 be an absolutely irreducible plane curve over Fix(o) (by which we imply in particular (a,P)~Fix(o)~ with f(a,B)=O.

f E Fix(o)[x,

y]). Then there exists

over K. Let K’ = K[x, y]/( f), and extend cr to CT’on K’ by a’(x) =x, o’(y) = y. So there exists (cc’,,!?‘)E Fix(o’)*, f(c~‘,/3’) =O, and this drops to the e.c. (K,a). 0

Proof. f is irreducible

Van den Dries showed me these in June 1990 (and Lascar noted it independently). Together they give something extremely suggestive.

A. MacintyrelAnnals

of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

Theorem 6. Zf (K, 0) is e.c., Fix(o)

is pseudojinite

165-180

169

(i.e. an infinite model of the theory

of jinite jields). Proof. See [2] for a proof that a field L is pseudofinite iff Aut(L”‘s/L) CYf, and every q absolutely irreducible plane curve over L has an L-rational point. Note.

It is quite easy to see (using Ax’s [l] characterization

of pseudofinite

fields) that every pseudofinite

of the absolute

L is elementarily

equivalent

for some e.c. (K, G). Just take K as an extension of r on the algebraic prime field of L, where Fix(r) is the field of absolute numbers of L. 1.3. o-action

in algebraic

numbers to Fix(o)

closure of the

geometry

Though it is not strictly necessary for the formulation of the crucial Axiom H, I find it valuable to give a systematic account of how rr E Aut(K), for K algebraically closed, induces

natural

actions in algebraic

1.3.1. CJacts on K” coordinatewise,

geometry

over K.

and on the power set of Kn by a(E) = {o(_?) :

TEE}. 1.3.2. ~7 acts on K[xl,. . .,x,1 by o on K, and the identity 1.3.3. If Zer( fi,.

on xi,. . . ,x,,.

..,fk)C K” is the set of zeros in K” of the fi E K[xI,. . . ,x,J, then

dZer(fi,...,fk)) = {dY):fi(Y))=

... =fk(Y)=O)

= Zer(fl( fl >,. . . , o( fk 1). 1.3.4. Thus, irreducibility.

r~ acts on A,(K) and P,(K), and TT acts on algebraic sets, respecting So rr is a homeomorphism for the Zariski topology, in both cases.

1.3.5. The a-action to radicals.

on K[xl , . . . ,x,1 extends to ideals, sending primes to primes, radicals

1.3.6. Evidently, 0 sends quasi-affine affine (respectively, quasi-projective)

(respectively, varieties.

quasi-projective)

varieties to quasi-

1.3.7. So g sends varieties to varieties [3, p. 151. Moreover, the action on polynomials extends to one on regular functions and morphisms, making cr functorial. Precisely: Let V be a variety, wlog affine, and U an open subset of V, containing the point P. Suppose f on U is given by g/h, g, h polynomials, h not vanishing on U. Then G(U) is an open subset of a(V) containing a(P), o(h) does not vanish on a(U), so O( f) =der o(g)/o(h) is (gives) a well-defined regular function at P.

and

This gives the action of o on regular functions. Notice that cr defines a continuous map (not a morphism) from V to o(V), and that for a regular function f : V -+ K, CJ(f) : (T(V) --) K is given by O( f) = afo-'. Now taking the definition of morphism of varieties given in [3, pp. 15, 161, f : VI ---f V2 is a morphism so is af g-’ =,+f c( f ).

170

A. Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

Now the functoriality 1.3.8.

0 has obvious

natural

of IJ is evident. action

ring isomorphisms

structure).

on the rings O(Y) ? U(a(Y))

This in turn induces

1.3.9. Similarly,

165-180

O(Y),

Y ranging

(not of course

over K-varieties, respecting

giving

the K-algebra

action on the local rings @~,r (E Q.(p),.(r)).

there is an obvious

1.3.10. (T respects rational, dominant nonsingularity).

action on the fields K(Y), and birational

Y a variety.

points, and respects singularity

(and

1.3.11. Now let V be a variety (construed as topological space), and 0~ its sheaf of regular functions, so cOv(U) is the ring of regular functions on U. Now cr : V ---)a(V) is continuous (as is o-l), and by [3, p. 651 the direct image sheaf o*(V) is o,(Ov)(W) = 0,(a-‘(IV)). One easily checks that QT(V)(W) = {ogc-’

: 9 E Q*(@)(W)}

and that hH o-‘ha defines a map Q,(v) -+ LT*(@v)of sheaves of rings on cr( V). So, in fact, (cr, h H o-‘ho) defines a morphism (actually an isomorphism) (K(%)-,(@U,4r(V,) of locally ringed spaces. Write 0(~,(%)=(4V,G,,,) and this is clearly functorial

on morphisms

of varieties.

1.3.12. In [3, p. 781 one deals with the fully faithful functor t from varieties to schemes over K. o is entirely compatible with this, as I now show. Firstly,

one associates

to any topological

space X a set t(X)

consisting

over K of all

nonempty irreducible closed subsets of X, and topologizes this by taking as closed subsets all t(Y), Y closed in X. t is functorial on continuous maps f, by defining t(f)(E), E nonempty irreducible closed, as the closure of f(E). One also defines a continuous cx:X + t(X) by setting a(P) equal to the closure of {P}. The scheme attached to V is (t(V),cr,(0~)). Now clearly, t(a)(E) = a(E) all E E t(V). Also, when U is open in t( I’), cr*(Sv)( U) = &(a-l(V)) and ~*(~0(V))(~(~)(~))

= QT(V,(~-‘t(@(U)) = {oga-’

: g E U)y(Cr-l(CL-l(t(0)(U))}

= {ago-’

: g E coV(a-‘(u))}.

A. MacintyrelAnnals

Since

the scheme

attached

171

of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997) 165-180

to o(V)

is t(o( V)), a*(Qv,),

of 1.3.11 of r~ on (V, 0~) extends to a sheaf isomorphism

we see that the action (also denoted

0)

(V)>~*(~v))-+(~(4~))?x*(Lo,(V~)) which is t(o)

on t(V),

and gives a map

~*(QT(V,) + a*(@*(&)) of sheaves of rings on t(V) by h I-+ t(a)-‘/n(o) as before. Again this is functorial. Moreover, t(V) =&f (t(V), a,(Uv)) has a natural structure of scheme over K, with the morphism to Spec(K) being (f, f’), where f sends every point of t(V)

to 0, the unique point of Spec(K),

and

f # : QSpec(K) + f*&(V) is given by f #(X) = the constant

function

on t(V) with value X.

On the other hand, r~ induces an automorphism of Spec(K) by (id,@). So one easily sees that 0 is even functorial on t at the level of schemes over K. 1.3.13. Finally, how does cr act on schemes over K? Let (X,0X)-+(,-f,+) Spec(K) be a scheme S over K. Composed with (id, g) this gives another scheme a(S) over K. Of course, 00-l IS the identity. We retrieve all the earlier nonsense via t! 1.4. The axiom Now we return to earth (and logic). Let V be a closed subvariety by equations fi(xl,..., xn)= ... = fk(x, ,..., x,)-O. I assume K algebraically defined by (~fl)(Yl,...,

(of1

)(Yl,

. ..)

closed. Then g(V)

Yn)=

‘..

=(~fk)(yl,...,yn)=0,

y,)=

...

=(cJfk)(y

,,...,

of A”(K) defined

is also a closed subvariety

of A”(K)

yn)=O.

a(V) shares with V all natural properties like nonsingularity, dimension Now form V x a(V), the closed subvariety of A2”(K) given by

d, etc.

=(~fk)(Yl,...,Yn)=O. Suppose,

W is a closed subvariety

w-Vxcr(V) 711J V

\

712

o(V)

of V x r~(V), and suppose the two morphisms

172

A. Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

are generically

surjective

(the xi are the natural projections).

point of W projects to generic points of V and a(V). intersects

165-180

This means that a generic

In this case, I say W potentially

the graph of cr.

Now I come to the axiomatic Axiom H. If W potentially

heart of the matter.

intersects

such that (x1 ,...,Xn,O(Xl),...,d(X,))E This extremely

the graph of (T, then there exists xl,. . . ,x,, E K w.

suggestive

principle

(in 1990) a more complicated version, order to axiomatize the e.c. (K,o).

was isolated involving

by Hrushovski,

various

V x o(V)

after I had used x . - . x am(V), in

It is crucial for what follows that one sees Axiom H as the conjunction of axioms Hk, for k= 1,2 ,..., where the Hk are (under the assumption that K is algebraically closed) first-order axioms. It is worth explaining this in some detail. Though I am only interested (now) in the case when K is algebraically closed, and the difference between variety and absolutely irreducible variety disappears, let me consider the variant of H where V and W are assumed absolutely irreducible. Fix an integer k and restrict H to the case in which there exists and n
1.5. Elimination

of quanti$ers

Lemma 5. Suppose

(K,o)

is e.c. Then Axiom

H holds in (K,o).

Proof. Suppose (K, a) e.c. Then K is algebraically closed. Go to a (K]+-saturated elementary extension (K, o) -t (KI, 01) [lo]. Then K1 contains a generic point (at,. . . , a,, PI,. . . , Pn) of W over K. We are using “generic” in the sense of [ 121. Now by generic surjectivity of ~1,712, (~(1, . . . ,a,) is V-generic over K and (fit,. . . , fin) is a~( V)-generic over K, i.e. a( V)-generic. Now define

d : K(Q ,...,a,)-~K(Bl,...,p,),

A. Macintyrel

Annals

of Pure and AppliedLogic 88 (1997) 165-180

by C’ = CJon K, o’(ai) = /3i. 0’ extends to an automorphism o”(4 ), . . . , a”(a,)) E W. Since (K, a) is e.c., we get some ..,4Y,))E

(Yl, ...,Yn,4YI)1. where yI,...,y,,EK.

173

(T” of Kl, and (~(1,. . . , a,,

w,

0

Now the crucial Nullstellensatz: Theorem 7. Suppose (K, C) satisJies Axiom H, and K is algebraically closed

Then

(K, o) is e. c. CT(D,)) be a basic system over K, with a solution Proof. Let C(vl, . . ..V.,~(Ul),..., a,) in an extension (L, a’) of (K, g) over K. Let V be the variety of (al,. . . , cc,,) (al,..., over K, so o(V) is the variety of (a’(~1 ), . . . ,~‘(a,)) over K, and let W be the variety of (c!,,..., a,,o’(al) ,...) cr’(a,)) over K. Then W 2 V x o(V). It is obvious that W potentially (P1,...,j3n)

meets the graph of O. So W has a K-point solves C.

(PI,. . .,/$,,o(/I~),

. . ., o(fin)), so

0

Note. 1. We use the assumption that K is algebraically closed to get V, W absolutely irreducible. 2. Inspection of the proof shows that in the above we can weaken H to H,,, where V, W are assumed nonsingular. The reason is that we can add to the equations for V (respectively (respectively, as usual.

W) inequations expressing that V (respectively, W) is nonsingular at cl (&o’(i)), and replace these inequations by equations in more variables

This shows that the class of e.c. (K, a) is elementary,

and so model-complete

[8]. So,

modulo Axiom H and the axioms that K is algebraically closed, every formula Q(V) is equivalent to an existential formula. We can do a little better, for the following reason. Lemma 8. Suppose (Kl,q), (K~,cz) are extensions of (Kj, ~3), where K3 is algebraically closed. Then (Kl, q), (K~,Q) can be jointly embedded in some W4,04

).

Proof. Trivial manipulation

of transcendence

bases over K3.

Cl

Corollary. If (Kl, 02) and (Kz, az) are e.c., and 01, CQagree on the algebraic closure of the prime jield then (Kl, rs1 ) 3 (K2,02). Proof. By Lemma

8 and model-completeness.

0

More generally, Lemma 8 shows that the (elementary) type of a tuple (al,. . . , a,) in an e.c. (K, o) is determined by 0 on the algebraic closure (in K) of the field generated

A. MacintyreIAnnals

174

of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

165-180

by the sequence. . . , &z, o(w),

al,.

o-‘(cq),...

. . .,4&z), ) 6’(an),

(i.e. the smallest

o2(a1 ), . . ., 02(%), . . .

a-2(q),

. . .) C2(cl,),

...

~1, . . . , ~1, and closed under

field containing

of course, leads one to a quantifier-elimination. obvious counterexample to quantifier-elimination

~,a-‘).

This remark,

What is required is suggested by an in the original language. Consider

Q(V) below. @p(u)Z o(u) = u A (3)(?

= lJA o(t) # t).

That one cannot eliminate the existential quantifier is seen by taking independent transcendentals ui and ~2, taking o as the identity on the algebraic closure of Ka(ui) (Ka the prime field), while taking o to fix K:“(u2) but move the square roots of u2, and then extend to an e.c. (K,cr’). The predicates I use for quantifier-elimination are natural generalizations of those used in the theory of pseudofinite fields [2]. Let it, k be nonnegative integers, and let f,gi,hi

(i,
be members

of

9.. . ,XOn,Xll ,...,~ln,yll,...,Yln,~2l,...,~Zn,Y2l,...,Y2n,...,

Xkl,...,Xkn,Ykl,...,Ykn,tl.

Let ShQ,i(u~,. . .,u,)

3t

be

d(Un),

f(Ul,...,

t) = 0

[

1

A A ((T(SI.(Ul,...,~-k(un),l))=hi(Vl,...,a-k(U,),t)) idm

where ui,,..,~-~

(u,) abbreviates

the sequence

9

of arguments

ul,...,Un,~(~l),...,~(~,),~-1(~l),...,~-’(~,),~2(Ul),...,~2(~,), 8(v1)

)...,

l+(u,),..

To formulate the extension notation is useful:

.,&I*),.

lemma

. .,(Tk(U,),a-k(u~) )...) dyu,). that gives quantifier-elimination,

the following

Definition 3. Let (K, o) be a difference field and X G K. Then (X), denotes the smallest subfield of K containing X and closed under e and 0-l. Lemma 9. Let (K, CJ) be a difference jield, Ko be the prime field of K, and X 2 K. Then (X), = K&Y, a(X), o-‘(X),

02(X), a-*(X),

. . .).

A. Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

Proof. Trivial. Lemma

175

165-180

0

10. Let Y be the relative algebraic closure of (X),

in K. Then (Y), = Y.

Proof. Suppose c( E Y. Then Bk,cr(B,)

WA,..., &I

), .*. 3 fJQ%f),

so CT(u) E Y.

(z(pk),~-l(B*),...,o-l(Bk),..., 0%

1,. . ., &AC),

and F a polynomial

for /h,...,fikEX,

F(o(B,),

,...,

. . . , ‘@k),

. . . ,a-‘+‘(jh

a) = 0

over Z. Then ), . . . , @-‘+‘(pk),

a(@))

= 0,

0

Lemma 11. Let (Ki,oi), i= 1,2 be dtjterence fields, Ki algebraically closed, and (Mi,ll/) dtjerence subjields of the respective (Ki,oi). Let 0: (Ml, $1)2:(A42,&) be an isomorphism of dtrerence ftelds, and suppose 0 respects all Sf,sk and TS~,~,~, (computed in the respective ambient Ki). Let h4; be the algebraic closure of Mr in Ki, and $: = o 1Mi. Then 0 extends to 0’: (Mi, &‘) N (AI,‘, *ii’>, 0’ also respecting the SrG,h and -SL8,i. Proof. By considering f = tP - x, we see that 0 respects being a pth power, so without loss of generality one can assume M/IMi is separable, 0’ will be constructed by a Tychonov argument, as a limit of extensions ON, where 0~ is defined on a finite Galois extension N of Mt. Fix such an N =A41 [a], say. Let F(t) = f (Yl, . ..> Yn,~l(Yl)r...,~l(Yn),~~l(Yl),...,~l-l(Y~),...,

)>. .

&Yl

2 &Yd,

qk(yl

>, . . ., qk(Yn>,

where F is over E, be the minimum normal closure Nr of Ml(a, q(a)). Then, by increasing a=goh,. &Yl

t),

polynomial

over A41 of some generator

(The latter is obviously

n, k if necessary

finite-dimensional

we can write

..,Yn,~l(Yl),...,~l(Yn),~~l(Yl),...,~~l(Y~),..., h f.. , &rn>>

qkbJ1

>, . . . >qk(Y?J?

6)

and 01 (a) = ho(Y1 ~~~.7Yn,~l1(Yl),~*~, &Yl),.

‘. 7 ~~:(Yn>, al-kh

with ga,hs over h. So M

~Sf,go,ha(Yl,...,Yn),

dYd>q’(n) ), . . . , al-k(Yn),

T..., 6)

a,-‘(Y,)

,...,

6 of the over Ml).

A. Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

176

165-180

whence

Obviously, f(@(Yl),

. . . > @(Yn),OZ(@(Yl)),.

&@h

is irreducible

>>>.

. .Y &@(Y,)),

..,02(~(yn)>,o~1(o(yI))

~$w(Yd),

,...,

. . ., q?o(y,)),

(T;l(o(y,))

,..‘)

t)

over A42. By the above, it has a root 6’ such that

(There may of course be several such roots 8.) If we choose one such 6’ then there is a unique field isomorphism 0’: Ml(S) N A42(8) extending 0, with O’(6) = 6’. Moreover, cQ(@‘(cc)) = O’(Oi(cc)). It may, however, happen that there is /3 in M,(6) and that oi(/?) is also in A41(6) and a2(@‘(/3)) # O’(oi(/?)). But, I claim there is a choice of 6’ such that this does not happen,

i.e. so that both

az(@‘(cc)) = @‘(o,(a)) and a2(@‘@>>

=

For, increasing P = (n(B)

@‘(w(B)).

n, k again if need be, we have

Sl(Yl,...,Yn,...,q =

h(Yl,.

-?Yl>,. . . ,Yn,.

. . , q-k(Yl),

. . >q-k(Yn),

6)

. . . , qk(Yn),

with 91, hi over 27. Let 8= (go,gl), i; = (ho,hi). Ml

8)

Then

i==f,g,~(YIMYn),

so

thereby clearly giving us 6’ that works for cc,p. There are only finitely many possible 8, so proceeding in this way we eventually get 8, and so O’, which works for all /3 such that p and o,(p) are in A&(d). Now let CIvary, and consider the projective system of all such 0’. Let 6 be a limit of this system. Then 6 is clearly a difference field isomorphism, evidently respecting all SJgh q 1 , and ~5”~i. I ,

A. Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

From this, Lemma

8, and the standard

criterion

165-180

177

[lo] for quantifier-elimination,

one

concludes: Theorem 12. The theory of e.c. (K, c) has quantzjier-elimination extra predicates

in the language with

for all Sf,g,r,.

1.6. Decidability We can prove decidability

of the theory

of all e.c. (K,a),

Lemma 7 or the preceding quantifier-elimination. Instead of the formulae Sr,g,i I now use sentence

using the corollary

to

S‘,#,a, where n = k = 0 (cf. intro-

duction of the predicates). So now f, S,i are polynomials over Z in a single variable. We know of course that two e.c. (Ki, ai) (i = 1,2) are elementarily equivalent if and only if they agree on such sentences Sf,g,h. But a little more is obvious on (short) reflection. We want to restrict somewhat the f we need consider. We restrict to f E Z[x] which satisfy: f is irreducible over Q, of degree m say, and with splitting field generated over Q by a single root c1 of f. Then the roots of f are ho(a), hl (a), . . . , h,_l(a) where each hi E Q[t], ho = t. Any 0 on Q(a) is determined by a choice of c( and one hi. If we do not specify E, but only hi, g is determined exactly up to conjugacy in Gal(Q(cc)). Now the algebraic closure UY’s of Q is a limit of such Q(a), compactness argument the conjugacy class of c in Gal(ClY’s) is Sf,s,h, where f ranges as above, g(t)=rt some r E Z, r# 0 and above are of form h/r, r E Z, h E Z[t].) But now it is clear that if (K, 0) is e.c., so is (K, z-‘oz) for any any p E Gal(Qa’s) extends to an automorphism of any algebraically

and by a simple determined by all h E Z[t]. (The hi r E Aut(K). Since closed K > Q, the

above yields, in characteristic 0, that the theory of an e.c. (K,o) is determined by the Sf,rt,h in it, as above. So, effectively any sentence @ is equivalent (in characteristic 0, and so in all characteristics Sf.,rl,h as above. So the decision

problem

p 3 PO(@), po recursive)

to a Boolean

combination

of

for @ reduces to

(i) Is Q, satisfiable in some characteristic p < PO(@)? (ii) Is the Boolean combination satisfiable in any other characteristic, including O? We may clearly assume, by loading a bit more into (i), that if Sf,rr,h or its negation occurs in the Boolean combination then r # 0 mod p for p 3 PO(@). For future reference (in [5]) we pay attention to the set of characteristics p in which @ is satisfiable, and if p#O we examine the possible restrictions to @” of cr satisfying

@.

Case (i): We examine each prime p< po separately. Fix one such. Now the discussion over Q can be replaced by one over EPp,considering f irreducible over EP (the assumption on generation by a single root is redundant), and we can clearly take

178

A. Macintyrel

f manic.

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997)

So now Q, is effectively

equivalent

need for r’s). But now by constructing and running

through

all (TE Gal(N)

to a Boolean

a finite extension

(all powers

165-180

combination

of Sf,t,h (no

N of lFP splitting

of Frobenius)

each

f,

we just test if Q, is

satisfiable. Case (ii): Without loss of generality, with the fi satisfying fi,

the earlier

Qi is a Boolean combination

conditions.

of S’,r,t,h, 1 6 i
Let L be the splitting

field over Q of

..,fN,presented effectively as Q[/3], with G(b) = 0, G manic irreducible

over Q.

We relegate to Case (i) any primes p for which the p-adic value of any coefficient of G is nonzero. Fix a /I, and effectively list the conjugates of p as F&3), . . . ,I$(/?), the L$ E Q[x], Fe(x) =x. Write all the roots of all the fi as polynomials Hil over Q in /I. Discard all primes p dividing the denominator of some coefficient of some such polynomial. The truth value of S’,r,t,h depends only on the restriction of o to L. This restriction is given by P H Fj(P)

some j,

and its action on all roots of the fi is explicitly

calculable.

In this way we can effec-

tively find the automorphisms

which satisfy @. This gives the decision procedure in characteristic 0, and in passing effectively describes the cr that satisfy Cp. These form a union of conjugacy classes. In finite characteristic we use Cebotarev’s Theorem. Note that if @ is not satisfiable in characteristic 0 then Qi is not satisfiable in characteristic p 3 pl(@), where pi is effectively calculable. Relegate the primes


surviving

prime).

We have the familiar

L -L,p-Fp

(*)

T

T

T

0 -

op-

Fp

EP the residue field of Lg. Suppose (TE Gal(L), o(P) = P. Then g extends uniquely to 5 E Gal(LpJQ&), which is naturally of order [Lq: Q,] (=ord(a)). Gal(LpIQ,) is naturally isomorphic to Gal( lF9)Fp), which is generated by x H x P, the Frobenius automorphism F’. This lifts back to a unique (~9 with op(Y)=P. As 9 varies above p, ~9 varies through a conjugacy class 9$ in Gal(L). Cebotarev’s Theorem [2] says that if %? is a conjugacy class in Gal(L), then the p with $, = 59 have density card(VQ/card(Gal(L)). In

A. MacintyrelAnnals

of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997) 165-180

179

particular, every u E Gal(L) is CJ~ for infinitely many 9’. I refer to the sets {p : %$= 9) as cebotarev sets. In particular, each of the conjugacy classes of automorphisms

has associated Consider

Cebotarev

sets.

first the j such that p -Fj(/?)

satisfies

@. Fix one such, and consider

(*), where 9 and p are chosen so that rsg is /? -4(/Q. It is quite evident that hold in (Ep,&). To deal with the finitely many my &,t,h, holding in (LB -g(p)) relevant SJ,,,, false in (L,/3 ++Z$(P)) we have to prepare a little, and discard some primes. Here is the procedure for dealing with one such S’,rt,h. Write the roots of f as polynomials Ht in a over Q, with coefficients integral for all surviving p. We have by assumption rN(4(P))

# h(N(B)),

so

G t (rHd4(t)) - Wfdt)). Since G is irreducible

over Q, we can find at(t), bt(t) E Q[t] so that

ar(tMt) + b/(t) . [rHI(f$(t)) - Wdt))l=

1.

Discard all p dividing any denominator of a coefficient of any at or bt. Then for the p surviving, ~&“,~~,h holds in (Eq,&). So we have shown (effectively) that, for all but finitely many p of the Cebotarev class attached to b-5(/3), @ is satisfiable in characteristic p by x H xp. Consider on the other hand, a LP’such that @Jis not satisfiable in characteristic p by x H xp on I&P,9 unramified. Then @ is not satisfied on L by 08, for the same reasons as above. Again,

if @ is satisfiable

in characteristic

p, it is by x ++xpm, some m, on lF9. As

above, it follows that o,$ satisfies @ in L. We have proved: Theorem 13. (a) The theory of e.c. (K,o)

of characteristic 0 is decidable.

(b) Given a sentence 8 the set of characteristics p in which 0 is satisjiable in an e. c. (K, CJ) consists of either (bl) a jinite set of finite characteristics, or (b2) the union of: {0}, a finite set of jinite characteristics, and a jinite number of effectively computable cebotarev sets for an eflectively computable L, possibly with finitely many effectively computable elements deleted. (c) The theory of all e. c. (K, a) is decidable. (d) Given 0 one can calculate an N and a prime po such that in all jinite characteristics p for which @ is satisfiable it is satisfiable by an extension of x H xP on IF ilg, tf p 2 pi, and by an extension of x H xPn on @, tf P-C pi, for some n
A.

180

2. Concluding

Macintyrel Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 88 (1997) 165-180

remarks

I expect to present, in [5], a proof that nonprincipal ultraproducts of fields (Kp, x H xp”‘), where K is algebraically closed of characteristic p, are e.c. provided the resulting

automorphism

Weil Conjectures,

is not a finite power

intersection

of Frobenius.

theory and desingularization.

The proof will use the By the preceding

it will

yield decidability of Frobenius, and, in characteristic 0, identify, up to elementary equivalence, nonstandard Frobenius with generic. Hrushovski [4] has independently obtained the same result, which is about to be submitted as this paper is being revised (February 1997).

Acknowledgements The research reported here was supported by a NSF grant to MSRI, by a Senior Research Fellowship of EPSRC, and by Merton College. This assistance is gratefully acknowledged. I am grateful to Gabriel Carlyle for helpful discussions, reading of earlier versions.

and for careful

References [1] [2] [3] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9] [lo] [l l] [12] [ 131

J. Ax, The elementary theory of finite fields, Ann. Math. 88 (1968) 239-271. M. Fried, M. Jarden, Field Arithmetic, Springer, Berlin, 1986. R. Hartshome, Algebraic Geometry, Springer New York, 1977. E. Hrushovski, The elementary theory of Frobenius, Preprints, Jerusalem (1996-1997). A. Macintyre, Nonstandard Frobenius and generic automorphisms, in preparation. B. Poizat, Groupes stables, Nur al-Mantiq wal-Ma’rifah, 2, Bruno Poizat, Lyon, 1987. M.O. Rabin, Decidable Theories, in: J. Barwise (Ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1977, pp. 595-629. A. Robinson, On the Metamathematics of Algebra, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1951. A. Robinson, On the concept of a differentially closed field, Bull. Res. Council of Israel Sect. F SF (1959) 113-128. G. Sacks, Saturated Model Theory, Benjamin, Reading, MA, 1972. H. Simmons, Existentially closed structures, J. Symbolic Logic 37 (1972) 293-310. A. Weil, Foundations of Algebraic Geometry, Amer. Math Sot. Colloq. Publ., vol. 29, American Mathematical Society, New York, 1946. A. Weil, Sur les courbes algkbriques et les vari&s qui s’en deduisent, Hermann, Paris, 1948.