672
Rejoinder Historical perspective cost-benefit analysis: David
Pearce
In a recent
paper
Doeleman’
in this journal,
has suggested
cost-beneht
analysis
‘mistaken environmental control
and
optimization argues,
by
so
on. only
as
level, “zoning
population
This
relates in nature
resource
macroenvironmental set.
‘micro’
set out
such
CBA
and
his
decisions
in Doeleman’s conditions serious
may
for
a
liveable
one and deserves
wider
society
CBA
is
a
comment.
arises
that
there
is nothing
critique
of CBA,
mean
although
repetition
is
unwelcome;
ingredients
of
an
macro’
approach
further
development
(a)
new in Doeleman’s
that
caveats
indicate this does
of
integrated already
not
important
(b) exist,
is needed;
that
ment London,
Pearce of
is Professor
Political Gower
of Economics,
Economy, Street,
London
University WClE
to
preferences
have
ie those
the
changed
CBA
through rate
being
taken
of
rate.
If
is ‘high’
the
the preferences
those
t +n from the standpoint at time t. Nonetheless,
to reappraise (the at
example
to
and
favour
stock
of
declines.
The
end
‘creeping
development’.
result
of using
6BT,
UK.
Page4 restated within
in which
work
the objective
to include which
known. the
assets
CBA
well to
of
to solve resources
Doeleman of
Talbot
of society
a conservation
standard
t +n
is a form
are,
refers
uses)
development,
and
however,
if the
at
environmental
problems
of the
Doeleman
more
is of
use of natural
t + n, then the generation
is likely the
the
use of natural
College
effect
to downgrade
arises
the
the discount
for the optimal
Depart-
with
generation-
though (c)
through
severely at
at
t +n
In its non-
works
at time t-account
discount
The
‘micro-
at time
of the current
the future
failure
solution
forces.
form,
preferences
resource
This
efficient
for
a proper
in
time”.” any
that ‘static
provide
t, say, is not efficient
when
is for
meaning
development
because
himself David
fails
over
habitats below
has
environ-
proposition
and of
option comments
CBA of
so as to solve
efficiency,
direction
the
Comment brief
basic
operates
generation
The
criti-
is not an
issues.
paternalistic
of a
breach
how
context
‘macroenvironmental’
will,
(indeed,
argument)
of
at a
level and that the summation
set of micro
way
which
of
the
Doeleman’s
time
basic
operates
mental
allocation
targets
Nonetheless, that
in
“dynamic
parks,
a theory
statement
efficiency’
Unfortunately,
does
point,
to
quotas
Doeleman be
which
as
how
negative
with
standards
and
not
he
CBA
in some
of CBA
Nothing new
mistaken
be corrected,
targets”.2
such
the
analysis’
ceilings,
to
as
sets environmental
pollution
are
advanced
supplementing
a broad
things
accurate
to
pollution
has
a caricature
in
such
‘macroenvironmental effectively
Doeleman
cized
applied
wilderness,
can
that
will result
when
issues of
Jacobus
that the use of
(CBA)
optimality’
preservation
on
and environmental comment on Doeleman
efficiency
is
target objec-
FUTURES December 1985
Rejoin&r-historical
tives are then pursued. That is, a set 01 boundaries are drawn round the project appraisal techniques and the techniques have then to operate within those constraints. The constraints are generally the same as those set out, rather vaguely, by Doeleman and, indeed, they are not precise in Page’s own work. Thus, Doeleman’s paper adds little in this general philosophical respect to Page’s 1977 work. In fact, however, there is even earlier work by this author which sets out the same problem in the context of pollution control. Pearce5 argued in 1976 that CBA will result in an inefficient solution to pollution problems as long as the objective of society is established so as to include some measure of survival capability. The basic idea is simple. CBA operates in the sphere of human values as expressed through actual or surrogate markets. Unless those preferences are based on a very ‘long view’ they wilt tend to ignore the relationship between the optimization of preferences viewed from the standpoint of the beginning of some time period, and the ecological requirements for long term survival.6 In terms of the current environmental fashion, Pearce was arguing that economic optimization in the CBA sense would not necessarily coincide with the ecological conditions for sustainability of society. In terms of pollution, those conditions require that waste should not be emitted to the environment in quantities greater than the assimilative capacity of the environment. The analogue for renewable resources is that harvest rates should not exceed natural or managed yields. Pearce’s 1976 work deliberately excluded the discount rate from the analysis, whereas Page’s work is very largely concerned with the effects of discount rates. We return to the discount rate below. For the moment, we observe the first proposition: Doeleman has not produced a statement which cannot be found in Page’s 1977 work, to which he refers, or Pearce’s 1976 work, to which he does not refer.
FUTURES December 1995
perspective and envimmenlal
cost-benefit analyris
673
New rules The rules required for the incorporation ‘macroenvironmental’ of considerations, or what we regard as ecological constraints, into CBA can be indicated. The basic requirement is sustainability, which we take to mean (i) conditions for the survival of mankind, and (ii) conditions for the tolerable survival of mankind. The latter, we argue, includes maintaining such things as genetic diversity as insurance against uncertainty, and environmental services for which mankind demonstrates either an explicit willingness to pay, or an option to pay (option value), or an intrinsic valuation of the environment in itselfexistence value. We may also add the value attributed by individuals to an asset for its purpose as a bequest to future generations-bequest value. All these concepts are well established in the literature, and there are attempts to measure them. 7 Prior conditions for tolerable survival are readily stated for the ‘renewable’ elements of the environment. As noted above, waste emissions must be less than the degrader capacity of the environment, and harvest rates must be less than or equal to yield rates. These are the essentials of ‘biological equilibrium’, although neither determines the optimal stock of environmental assets (yields will often be stock-dependent), a subject we cannot develop in a short set of comments. Pearce, in a later paper, suggests that we can actually formulate pricing rules which accommodate the sustainability criteria.8 nonFor renewable resources the issue is different since any harvest rate reduces the stock, whether we think of stocks of blue whales or the stock of environment for wastes that have no counterpart degrader capacity in the environment (mercury, cadmium etc). In this context we have to resort to some concept of intergenerational fairness, which is how Page deals with it, or to a set of generic rules that basically ‘forbid’ irreversible activities,
or to amended CBA rules which do allow us to treat irreversibility in a more sophisticated way. The straw man of CBA The last point we make is that Do&man has an outmoded conception of CBA. Although he refers to some of the recent literature he has not absorbed one of its central messages. (Indeed, Doeleman greatly exaggerates even the practical use of CBA. In the UK it is a rarity, not the norm for decision aids.) First, what partly troubles him is that CBA incorporates a discount rate greater than zero. Indeed, he seems to think that CBA somehow logically entails ‘high’ discount rates, perhaps approximating market rates of interest. Yet this is true if, and only if, one takes a particular view of how to derive discount rates-ie by looking at the marginal productivity of capital-although even then it is not evident that even this approach dictates high real rates of discount. Even if it did, there is nothing in the logic of CBA that observation of such rates. requires Observation of normative rates based on social preferences could readily give rise to very low rates. Rates based on social time preference, for example, typically contain two components such that the social discount rate equals the sum of some measure of ‘impatience’ (the pure time preference rate) and the rate of of consumption. of utility growth Arguments about the ethical relevance of the former are well known. The latter can readily produce very low rates if economic growth prospects are poor, and will produce very low rates in many developing countries. The essential point is that CBA does not logically entail my particular discount rate. However, even if we adopt what Doeleman believes to be conventional and ‘high’ discount rates, does CBA necessarily dictate ‘creeping development’? Here it is slightly surprising that Doeleman has missed the message of the work of Krutilla and Fisher to which he refers,” perhaps because he has not
pursued the development of that work since 1975. The point of this work is that the decision to develop or conserve, using CBA, will not result in a compromise of some development and same conservation. Yet Doeleman’s whole analysis is based on the assum~t~an that compromise is the outcome of CBA-eg in his land use example . . . “C/B economics presents a set of recommendations, predictably amounting to aform of compromise . . “.* Yet the KrutillaFisher algorithms are quite clear in that, while they could result in some development and some preservation, the phenomenon of i~eoers~b~lity whereby development precludes anyone ever securing the benefits of preservation is highly likely to dictate corner solutions in which development is postponed altogether. Indeed, the conditions for this result to converge to a result in which development is neuer permitted, are set out by Porter in an excellent exposition and extension of Krutilla and Fisher’s work.” The mechanism at work is very much one in which delay increases the value of information about the benefits of preservation, Moreover, the preference system is biased in favour of preservation and against development. Doeleman notes the latter for developed countries but argues it is not likely to occur in developing countries, Yet even here he is issuing warnings which are well known. Much of what is happening in the Sahel, for example, has risen from a failure to recognize the requirements for biological equiiibrium.i2 That failure has nothing to do with CBA: forest clearance for agriculture in the Sahel or in Brazil, for example, has not been justified on CBA grounds but on grounds of macroeconomic ob_jectives which reveal limited or non-existent understanding of the ecological requirements for survival. In short, the sustainability criteria have not been met and the experience of these countries shows just how quickly the ill-effects of non-observance of the constraints arise. But this brings us full
FUTURES December 1985
Rejoinder-hisforicai
circle to Doeleman’s central point. Essentially, he is correct, but not new, not sufficiently constructive, and certainly unfair to CBA. References 1. J Doeleman, “Historical perspective cost-benefit and environmental analysis”, Futures, 17 (2), April 1985, pages 149-163. 2. Ibid, page 161. 3. Ibid, page 152. 4. T. Page, Conservation and Economic Efficiency (Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977). “The limits of cost5. D. W. Pearce, benefit analysis as a guide to environmental policy”, Kyklos, 29, Fast 1, 1976. 6. That myopia results in inefficient longrun welfare maximization reprdless of any ecological implications is well known in the economics literature. See R. Strotz, “Myopia and inconsistency in dynamic utility maximization”, Review of Economic Studies, 23, 1955-1956. R. Bishop, “Option 7. See for example, value: an exposition and extension”, Land Economics, 58, February 1982 8. D. W. Pearce, “Optimal prices for sustainable environments”, mimeo, University College, London, 1985. Krutilla and A. C. Fisher, 9. J. The Economics of Natural Environments (Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975). For a more recent statement see A. C. Fisher and J. Krutilla, “The economic theory of nature preservation”, in A. V. Kneese and J, L. Sweeney, Handbook of Natural Resource and Energy Economics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, forthcoming. 10. Doeleman, op tit, page 155. 11. R. Porter, “The new approach to wilderness preservation through benefit-cost analysis”, Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 9, 1982. 12. See D. W. Pearce and A. Markandya, “Natural resource depletion in developing countries”, University College London, mimeo, 1985.
The author
replies
Pearce’s postscript “Historical perspective and environmental cost-benefit
FUTURES December 1985
perspective and cnvironmmtal cost-bcncjif analysis
675
analysis: comment on Doeleman” * indicates a measure of agreement on both the relevance and validity of the proposition that economic optimization per se would not necessarily coincide with the ecological conditions for sustainability of society. There is less agreement when Pearce claims that there is nothing new in this insight and that, indeed, hefollowed by others-has said as much in 1976.* He also argues that an interpretation of cost-benefit analysis (CBA) which emphasizes a microeconomic approach coupled with high rates of discount, does not do justice to recent developments in the technique. In reaching this conclusion, however, the position I have taken3 would appear to have been distorted. In his first paragraph, Pearce sets out that: Doeleman has suggested that the use of CBA will result in ‘mistaken optimality’ when apphed to environmental issues such as the preservation of wilderness, pollution control and so on. This mistaken optimisation can only be corrected, he argues, by supplementing CBA with ‘macroenvironmental analysis’ which effectively sets environmental standards on a broad level, and relates to such things as zoning as in nature parks, pollution ceilings, resource quotas and population targets (my emphasis). Two
corrections
and contrary
are in order to the above,
here.
I have
First, stated:
What is being argued here is based on the possibility of environmental standards eroding and not the necessity of this happening. In other words, the paradigm rest on inductive observation of what is happening rather than on deductive analysis of what must happen.
Historical evidence strongly points towards ‘mistaken optimality’ on account of a deterioration of environmental optima during this century. Of late, the media debate on the dying of the Black Forest in FR Germany as well as the most recent OECD pollution projections to the year 20004 reinforce this assessment. Second, in summing up my position, Pearce claims that I have argued that
676
Rejoinder-historical perspectiveand anvironmenfalcast-bene@ analysis
only so called macroenvironmental standards can offer correction. This is not so. Macroenvironmental standards are presented not as the only(!) but as the favoured solution. The difference allows Pearce to take issue with my supposedly having neglected what is, it would seem, his favoured solution: namely, to expand -as in literature quoted by him and myself-a narrow pragmatic microapproach to CBA by such methods as the incorporation of wider constraints; the measurement of option values in order to assess the consequences of irreversible actions; the employment of low or zero rates of discount, and so on. Indeed, one might be led to believe that I am opposed to the application and further development of CBA. academic In spite of worthwhile refinements in the theory, sight should not be lost of the political reality of the formal and widespread informal practice of CBA. Precisely for this reason I have sought to put the use of CBA in a historical perspective. Perhaps, therefore, Professor Pearce’s interest in CBA is more analytical, whereas mine is more political. For instance, Pearce writes that: He (Doeleman)
seems to think that CBA
somehow logically entails rates, perhaps approximating interest.
‘high’ discount market rates of
Of course, it goes without saying that one cannot rule out low or zero or, for that matter, negative discount rates on logical grounds. But my grounds are historical. One may observe how high discount rates (from an environmental point of view) have prevailed in CBA as they have in business and in political calculations. Furthermore, I have tried to argue why, ceteris @bus, this is likely to continue to be the case in the future. Finally, Pearce regrets that “Doeleman does not set out a theory of how such macroenvironmental targets are to be set”. A tall order. On the other hand, I have endeavoured to outline a number
of pertinent features of a preferred These policy. macroenvironmental features include the basis of such a policy in the decisions of ‘wise men and women’; the possibility of consistency with decentralized market or laissez-faire the conceivably pluralistic principles; nature of the policy’s effects; the scope for gradualism; and the vital need for protection against unqualified majority opinion. To my mind, the formulation of macroenvironmental targets is not so much a matter of theoretical deduction (as Pearce is seeking) but one of ethical choices in the interests of generations to come. Whether or not all this amounts to “nothing new” seems to be of limited Important is the warning consequence. that, by itself, pragmatic CBA can and does lead to wholly inadequate environmental decision making in the long run without there being sufficient awareness of this danger within or beyond the economics profession. It may be that to deal with this potentially disastrous inadequacy in environmental decision are changes institutions making, required which involve the incorporation of quantitative and qualitative environmental standards or safeguards in the constitution of countries with the wish to so approach a voluntary future.
References “Historical perspective and environmental cost-benefit analysis: comment on Doeleman”, above. D. W. Pearce, “~helimitsofcost-ben~~t analysis as a guide to environmental policy”, Kyklos, 29(l), 1976. J. A. Doeleman, “Historical perspective cost-benefit environmental and analysis”, Futures, 17 (Z), April 1985. Organisation of Economic Cooperation and Development, Second EnvironmentaE Report to the ~~v~~on~~t Ministers Countries, June 1985.
ofMember
Ja~obus Doeleman University of NCWLXZ& NSW
2308,
Australia
FUTURES December 1985