Representation in majority tournaments

Representation in majority tournaments

Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35–53 www.elsevier.nl / locate / econbase Representation in majority tournaments Gilbert Laffond a , *, Jean L...

115KB Sizes 1 Downloads 83 Views

Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35–53 www.elsevier.nl / locate / econbase

Representation in majority tournaments Gilbert Laffond a , *, Jean Laine´ b a

´ , Conservatoire National des Arts et Metiers ´ Laboratoire d’ Econometrie , 2 Rue Conte´ , 75003 Paris, France b ´ , Campus de Ker Lann, ENSAI and CREST – Laboratoire de Statistique et Modelisation Rue Blaise Pascal, 36170 Bruz, France Received 1 February 1997; received in revised form 1 June 1998; accepted 1 December 1998

Abstract The paper presents a general setting for studying majority-based collective decision procedures where the electorate is divided into constituencies according to an equal-representation principle. It generalizes the well-known Referendum Paradox to the non-dichotomous choice case, and shows that all Condorcet choice rules are sensitive to the design of the apportionment of the electorate, in the sense that final outcomes may entirely differ from those prevailing when there is a single constituency. Direct and representative democratic systems thus lead to mutually inconsistent collective decisions.  2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Representation; Majority voting; Tournament choice

1. Introduction Representational democracy refers to multi-step collective choice procedures: in the first step, individuals are allocated among committees or constituencies, each one sending one or several representatives in charge of their constituents’ interests in the higher levels; then representatives are themselves allocated among committees, such a process going on until some decision is finally taken. In the case where collective decisions rest on the majority rule, the formal structure of such a representational system in the dichotomous choice case has been investigated by Murakami (1966); Fishburn (1971); Fine (1972). These studies complete May’s characterization of simple majority rule (see May, 1952) by considering the representative (or indirect) majority rule obtained by repeated applications of the simple majority decision rule. Representational *Corresponding author. 0165-4896 / 00 / $ – see front matter  2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PII: S0165-4896( 99 )00007-4

36

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

democracy is defined ‘‘as a hierarchy of voting procedures, each of which may be called a council.. Every individual casts a ballot or ballots in one council or councils. A decision in each council is represented in a higher council whose decision is, in turn, represented in a still higher council and so on’’ (Murakami, 1966, pp. 710–711). This axiomatic study involves no restriction on the way committees are initially designed: in particular, some individuals may belong to several committees, and committees may be of different sizes. This paper is restricted to the study of two-step procedures, where, in the first step, the electorate is partitioned into constituencies, each one sending a single representative in charge of her constituents’ interests within the final choice made by representatives in the second step. Moreover, it tackles the question of how to design a representational system in a ‘consistent’ way. A possible approach to such a consistency concept is the following: let us consider the number of representatives as a fixed parameter R, and suppose that the number C of constituencies is imposed by the polity; the problem is then to design a ‘satisfactory’ mechanism which allocates the R representatives among constituencies. ‘Satisfactory’ may here rest on basic constitutional principles such as the fact that representatives should be allocated among constituencies according to their relative population sizes. Such an approach reduces to the ‘fractional problem’ which arises when the ratio C /R is not an integer: how to allocate representatives when the exact egalitarian apportionment is impossible? The reader may refer to Balinsky and Young (1975), (1982) and the references quoted there for details. In this paper, we follow a different approach. We still consider the number of constituencies as exogenously given, and we suppose that the apportionment of the electorate among them satisfies the above equal representation principle. Our purpose is to compare the way direct (referendum-type) and representational voting systems behave for some given preference profile in the electorate. In other words, we are interested in the study of referenda outcomes in representational democracies. It is well known that, in the case of a dichotomous collective choice problem, it may well happen that the majority of voters favors an opinion whereas the majority of representatives its negation. Such a situation is closely related to the so-called ‘Ostrogorski Paradox’, and is introduced as the ‘Referendum Paradox’ in Nurmi (1998).1 The following simple example illustrates this potential inconsistency: let us consider a 9-voter electorate facing h0,1j as choice set; the next matrix summarizes the individual asymmetric preferences (where a cell labelled 0 corresponds to a voter preferring 0 to 1): 0 0 0

1 0 1

1 1 0

Then an overall majority prefers outcome 0 to outcome 1, which means that 0 is the 1

Nurmi (1998) provides a comparative analysis of several voting paradoxes in the case of dichotomous choice; see also Nurmi (1997) on the referendum paradox.

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

37

referendum winner. Now, if the apportionment is designed according to the three columns, and if each constituency is represented by a single representative who votes consistently with the majority of her constituents, then 1 defeats 0 under representational democracy. This paradox, and close versions of it, have been extensively studied by Ostrogorski (1903); Anscombe (1976); Daudt and Rae (1976); Deb and Kelsey (1987); Nermuth (1992); Nurmi (1998). It describes the well-known sensitivity of representational democratic outcomes to the design of apportionments. The primary goal of the present paper is to extend the analysis of the referendum paradox to the case of more than two outcomes, and where the collective decision procedure is based on the simple majority rule. Formally, we consider a finite set N of n voters (where n is odd) who have to select one or several outcomes among a finite set X. Each voter has preferences over X represented by a complete linear order. In a direct democratic system, or referendum,2 individual preferences induce a complete asymmetric binary relation on X, called a tournament T, which states that outcome x dominates outcome y whenever more than one half of voters prefer x to y. However, the referendum problem does not reduce to identifying a maximal element of X for T : it is well-known that such a maximal element, called a Condorcet winner, may not exist, for nothing precludes T to be cyclic. Therefore, choosing from a tournament entails no natural procedure or solution. A tournament solution is formalized as a multi-valued mapping S from the set of all possible tournaments on X, to X. A rather large literature is devoted to the search for Condorcet-consistent tournament solutions (i.e. those solutions which select the Condorcet winner whenever it exists) tournament solutions. This line of research has been drawn either on axiomatic grounds (see, for example, Moulin, 1986; Dutta, 1988; Schwartz, 1990; Laffond et al., 1995, 1996), or on strategic grounds (see Banks, 1985; Fisher and Ryan, 1992, 1995a,b; Laffond et al., 1993, 1994).3 To summarize, for any preference profile aggregated into a tournament T, S(T ) represents the referendum outcome for some collective choice procedure S. This setting is easily adapted to a representational democracy. Suppose that one has to divide the electorate N into K mutually disjoint subsets of odd and equal cardinality Nk , 1 # k # K, where K is exogenous.4 The fact that each constituency contains an odd number of voters precludes ties in pairwise majority comparisons of outcomes. Therefore, voters’ preferences in constituency Nk lead to a tournament T k on X. Furthermore, let S be the prevailing choice concept in the society. We introduce here two specific methods for selecting the final set of winners given the family hT 1 ,...,T K j of tournaments. The first one is called the ‘one-shot method’ and is defined as follows: the representative of constituency Nk reports her constituents’ preferences by announcing T k . Then, two outcomes x and y are finally compared according to the majority rule applied to all representatives. Formally, x will defeat y in the society if x is preferred to y in more than 0.5K constituencies. Since n and all uNk u are odd integers, this defines a new tournament TA on X, called tournament among representatives, which is used to define 2

Referendum naturally refers to the dichotomous case. For simplicity, we keep the word for the general case study. 3 Laslier (1997) offers a complete presentation of this literature. 4 Note that we avoid the fractional problem suggested above.

38

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

the final set S(TA ) of winners, called the representational or indirect outcome. This method is a natural extension of the dichotomous case illustrated above, and corresponds to the actual practice of the parliamentary type. The second method, called the sequential choice method, endows each constituency with the power to influence the final agenda. We suppose that the actual choice set X* open to representatives (or actual agenda) is a subset of X (which is interpreted as the set of all ex ante candidates). A potential candidate belongs to the actual agenda if it is supported by at least one constituency Nk [i.e. belongs to S(T k )]. Thus, for a given apportionment A 5 hN1 ,...,Nk j, the actual agenda is defined by X* 5 < 1#k #K S(T k ); the set of final winners is then defined by S(TA /X*), which is the set of S-winners in the tournament among representatives restricted to the actual agenda. Such a choice method obviously coincides with the previous one in the dichotomous case. It may be conceived as a model of internal democratic organization within political parties: viewing constituencies as local committees having charge of the definition of the party policy platform, the final step would correspond to the party congress where the assembly of all local representatives choose among all proposals made by local committees.5 Having specified what is the final outcome (for some district map) of a representational system, we can now study the referendum paradox with at least three candidates. The paper mainly addresses the following question: is it always possible, given some preference profile, to design an apportionment such that direct and representational outcomes both coincide (or at least intersect)? The answer is trivially positive in the dichotomous choice case. We show below that this is no longer true in a higher dimensional setting. When dealing with the one-shot rule, a sufficient condition for avoiding the referendum paradox is to choose an apportionment A such that T and TA are identical. We call such an apportionment representative. Hence the problem becomes the following: does at least one representative apportionment exist for any preference profile? We exhibit (Theorem 2) a profile for which this is not the case. Moreover, we show (Theorems 5 and 6) that, when the candidate set is larger than three, direct and indirect outcomes may be disjoint for any district map (with a fixed number of constituencies), and for any Condorcet-consistent solution. These general inconsistency results are obtained in the case where no restriction bears upon the individual preferences. One may look for domain restrictions which ensure identical direct and indirect outcomes. For instance, it is easy to check that, in the dichotomous case, one cannot have one candidate supported by more than 2 / 3 of the electorate and the other supported by more than 2 / 3 of the representatives. More generally, a widespread social agreement allows avoidance of the referendum paradox for any district map. It is shown in Wagner (1983), (1984); Nurmi (1998) that such agreement corresponds to a qualified majority of 3 / 4 of the electorate. We prove below that this ‘75% rule’ still applies in the general case (Theorem 3). More precisely, we

5

Political parties, such as the French socialist party, are regularly involved in arbitration procedures among several militant tendencies. The actual agenda may be interpreted as the set of all those tendencies which emerge from local debates. We provide below an alternative interpretation of the sequential choice rule.

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

39

show that, for any majority margin lower than 75%, there exists a profile allowing for no representative apportionment (Theorem 4). Turning to the sequential choice rule, it appears that an even larger discrepancy exists between direct and representational system. Indeed, we show that direct and indirect outcomes may not overlap even for profiles allowing for any apportionment to be representative (Theorem 7). Thus the sufficient condition for no paradox in the one-shot rule case does not apply to the sequential rule one. Consistency between direct and representational outcomes may be conceived as a normative criterion for collective choice. A related separability axiom has been introduced by Smith (1973) for the dichotomous choice case: it states that, whenever the electorate is divided into two constituencies in such a way that both choose the same candidate, then the society should choose accordingly. This axiom is easily extended to more than two candidates: the society should choose the intersection between the constituency choice outcomes. It is already known (see Young, 1975) that no Condorcet-consistent solution verifies this generalized version of Smith’s axiom. Our consistency requirement between direct and representational outcomes goes in the reverse direction: whenever the overall society chooses some set of candidates, there is a way to design local bodies such that this set coincides (or at least intersects) with a specific subset of all candidates chosen in at least one local body. We then prove that this consistency axiom is incompatible with Condorcet-consistency. Finally, one may argue that, despite all distortions just listed, most polities does rest on a representational system. Hence, the main criterion is not the consistency between direct and indirect outcomes, but instead the sensitivity of the indirect outcome to some change in the district map. We prove (Theorem 9) that any Condorcet-consistent solution is sensitive to such a change. Indeed, we exhibit a profile for which any apportionment is representative, whereas the outcomes of any two different apportionments are mutually disjoint. The paper is organized as follows: Section 2 formalizes all concepts described in the introduction. Section 3 is devoted to the existence of representative apportionments. The study of the referendum paradox, as well as the analysis of sensitivity of representational outcomes to the district map, appear in Section 4. The paper ends with comments on directions for further research.

2. Representativeness concepts We now introduce several concepts dealing with representation in a majority voting system. Let us begin with simple notions about tournaments. Consider a population N5h1,...,i,...,nj of n voters (where n is odd). Each voter i has preferences over a finite set X of social alternatives (or candidates), which are represented by a complete linear order s i on X. A profile [s]5(s i ) i [N is a vector of n preference orders on X. The set of all possible preference profiles is denoted by P (N). Now with each profile [s][ P may be associated the complete asymmetric binary relation T(s) on X (called the majority tournament for [s]) defined by: ;x,y[X, xT(s)y⇔uhi [N:xs i yju.0.5n. Inversely, it is well-known that, as long as the number n

40

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

of voters can be chosen large enough, every tournament T on X corresponds to some preference profile [s], i.e. ' a finite set of integers N and [s][ P (N) such that T5T(s) (see MacGarvey, 1953). The first definition introduces a restriction on profiles which is useful for the sequel: Definition 1. Let a .0.5n. A preference profile [s] is said to have strength a if ;x,y[X, xT(s)y⇔uhi [N:xs i yju. a. Let D [resp. D (a )] denote the set of all tournaments on X (resp. of all tournaments on X associated with profiles of strength at least a ).6 A tournament solution is a multivalued application S from D to X. The set of S-winners of T [ D is the subset S(T ) of X. Furthermore, if X9,X and T [ D, we denote by S(T /X9) the set of S-winners of T once restricted to the subset X9 of candidates. A Condorcet-winner of X for T [ D is a candidate x*[X such that x*Tx;x±x*. A tournament solution S is Condorcet-consistent if it always selects the Condorcet-winner as unique winner whenever it exists. Furthermore, a solution S9 is said to be finer than solution S (denoted by S9#S) if for any tournament T on X, S9(T )#S(T ). A large and growing literature is devoted to the search for a ‘satisfactory’ Condorcet-consistent solution concept, satisfactory meaning based on relevant and desirable axioms for collective choice. Special attention will be paid below to a specific solution concept, the Uncovered Set (see Miller, 1977, 1980; ´ 1994), which is defined Shepsle and Weingast, 1982; Moulin, 1986; Laffond and Laine, as follows: Definition 2. Let T [ D. The covering relation → is defined on X 2 by: x→ y⇔xTy and [;z[X, yTz⇒xTz]. The Uncovered Set of X for T is the set UC(T )5hx[X: there is no y[X such that y→xj. Almost all Condorcet-consistent solutions proposed in the literature are finer than the Uncovered Set (the only exception is the top-cycle). Let us turn now to several concepts related to the design of a representative democratic system. Many alternative ways to divide the electorate N into mutually disjoint subsets (or constituencies) may be a priori conceived. The following one involves rather weak requirements: Definition 3. A K-apportionment of N is a partition A5hN1 ,...,Nk j of N into K non-empty subsets called constituencies such that 2;k[h1,...,Kj, n k 5uNk u is odd, and 2;k,k9[h1,...,Kj, n k 2n k9 #2. A K-apportionment is perfect if ;k,k9[h1,...,Kj, n k 5n k 9 . Moreover, it is non-degenerated if K ±1,n. The set of all possible apportionments of N is denoted by G (N). Such a definition can be motivated as follows: in order to choose one or several candidates within X, the society implements a two-step voting process where:

6

We are not interested here with the fact that D(a ) may be a proper subset of D for some values of a.

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

41

• in the first step, voters, once allocated in constituencies, ask a representative to promote their opinions (i.e. their preferences over X) in parliamentary debates; • in the second step, the final choice is made from all representatives’ opinions about candidates. We obviously restrict our analysis to non-degenerated apportionments. Majority voting within each constituency Nk will generally leads to a non-transitive binary relation on X. The first condition in Definition 3 implies that it will lead to a tournament T k (s) defined as the restriction of T(s) to Nk (i.e. xT k (s)y⇔uhi [Nk : xs i yju.0.5n k ). Hence, a representative’s opinion is a tournament on X. Since we suppose that n is odd, it follows that K is also odd. A perfect apportionment implies that each representative represents the same number of voters. This ‘equal weight’ requirement for representatives ensures that each individual preference is given ex ante the same potential influence on final decisions. However, perfectness implies some restriction on the electorate size. This explains the second condition in Definition 3, which formalizes an ‘almost equal representation principle’. It is worth noting that none of the inconsistency results obtained below rests on the necessity to design constituencies of unequal sizes: indeed, all proofs involve perfect apportionments. In order to make precise the actual choice process considered here, we define the notion of tournament among representatives as follows: Definition 4. Let [s][ P (N). Let A5hN1 ,...,NK j be a K-apportionment of N. The tournament among representatives is the complete asymmetric binary relation TA (s) on X defined by: xTA (s)y⇔uhk[h1,...,Kj: xT k (s)yju.0.5K. This means that an outcome x will be socially preferred to an outcome y if x defeats y in more than one half of constituencies under majority rule. Now suppose that S has been chosen by the society as the relevant choice concept. We now formalize two alternative choice methods which may prevail in a representational system:

2.1. The one-shot method It consists in choosing the set of winners from the tournament among representatives (instead of from the initial tournament in a direct democracy). This leads to the following definition: Definition 5. Let [s][ P (N) and A[ G (N). The set of S-winners in the one-shot method is defined by S[TA (s)]. The initial majority tournament T(s) generally differs from the tournament among representatives TA (s). This suggests an additional restriction on the design of apportionment.

42

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

Definition 6. Let [s][ P (N). An apportionment A is said to be representative if T(s)5TA (s). GR (N,s) denotes the set of all representative apportionments of N.7 This representativeness concept states that voters are allocated among constituencies in such a way that majority opinions are not biased through representation, in the sense that pairwise majority comparisons are identical in both representational and referendum systems. Note that, in the dichotomous case, the referendum paradox amounts to the existence of at least one non-representative apportionment.

2.2. The sequential choice method Another way to design the choice process is to select within each constituency a set of winners, and then, at the final level, to choose the set of finally elected candidates among those previously chosen at the constituency level. Therefore, for a given profile [s], S[T k (s)] represents the set of elected candidates in constituency Nk . As long as there is no strategic bias in the representation process, each N k -representative then supports S[T k (s)] as the set of best candidates. This means that < 1#k #K S[T k ( s )] is the set of candidates among which the final choice will prevail. These candidates are then compared according to TA (s): indeed, xTA (s)y means that more than one half of representatives (or constituencies) prefer x to y. This is formalized in the next definition: Definition 7. Let [s][ P (N) and A5hN1 ,...,Nk j[ G (N). The set of finally elected candidates through the sequential choice method is defined by S(TA (s) / < 1#k #K S[T k ( s )]). Note that in the dichotomous case, the sequential and the one-shot methods coincide. It is straight-forward to exhibit a profile for which this is no longer the case for more than two outcomes and some Condorcet-consistent solution. It is now possible to formalize the way to compare referendum and representational systems, and more generally the sensitivity of final choices to the apportionment procedure. The next definition deals with the one-shot method: Definition 8. A Condorcet-consistent solution S is neutral to apportionment if for any electorate N, ;[s][ P (N), there exists A[ G (N) such that S[TA (s)]5S[T(s)]. Furthermore, S is weakly neutral to apportionment if ;N, ;[s][ P (N), 'A[ G (N) such that S[TA (s)] > S[T( s )]±[. When the one-shot method is used, both systems allow for the same set of final outcomes as long as the apportionment is representative. Moreover, such a set is not sensitive to the choice of a specific representative apportionment. In other words, an electoral reform does not matter as long as the representativeness property is not violated. The next two definitions deal with the sequential choice method: 7

Note that, since it relates the apportionment to some given profile, this representativeness concept cannot be used as a guideline for real world institutional design: district maps are drawn to endure over diverse issues and preference profiles.

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

43

Definition 9. A Condorcet-consistent solution S is sequentially neutral to apportionment if for any electorate N, ;[s][ P (N), there exists A[ G (N) such that S(TA (s) / < 1#k#K S[T k (s)])5S[T(s)]. Furthermore, S is weakly sequentially neutral to apportionment if ;N, ;[s][ P (N), 'A[ G (N) such that [S(TA (s) / < 1#k #K S[T k (s)])] > S[T( s )] ± [. A solution is neutral (or sequentially neutral under the sequential rule) to an apportionment if it selects the same set of winners in both referendum and representational systems. It is weakly neutral (or sequentially neutral) to an apportionment if the two sets of final outcomes intersect. Whenever uXu52, any Condorcet-consistent solution S is neutral to any representative apportionment. We will see below that this is no longer true for larger sets of candidates. Another sensitivity concept is defined as follows: Definition 10. Let S, G (N). A Condorcet-consistent solution S is non-sensitive to S if ;[s][ P (N), ;A5hN1 ,...,Nk j, A95hN 19 ,...,N K9 9 j[S, S(TA (s) / < 1#k #K S[T k (s)])5 S(TA9 (s) / < 1#k 9#K 9 S[T k ( s )]). Furthermore, S is weakly non-sensitive to S if ;A5hN1 ,...,Nk j, A95hN9 1 ,...,N 19 ,...,N K9 9 j[S, [S(TA (s) / < 1#k #K S[T k ( s )])] > [S(TA9 ( s ) / < 1#k 9#K 9 S[T k9 ( s )])] ± [. A solution S is non-sensitive to a set of apportionments if it provides the same set of winners whatever the actual apportionment that prevails among admissible ones. It is weakly non-sensitive if any pair of apportionments share at least one winning outcome. The informal idea which underlines this definition is that, even if the choice between a direct and an indirect democratic system does influence the finally elected candidate(s), the latter should not change in case of a reform of the apportionment method. Such a requirement allows for restricting the set of potentially admissible electoral reforms. Our approach to the representative voting systems naturally suggests the following questions, which are studied in the next two parts: • Is it true that for any preference profile, there exists a representative apportionment? If not, is it possible to define a non-obvious restriction on the set of profiles which ensures the existence of such a representative apportionment? • Does the representativeness requirement for apportionment matter? In particular, is it possible, for both collective choice methods defined above, to exhibit a profile for which a Condorcet-consistent solution is non-neutral to any non-representative apportionment? • Can we find a Condorcet-consistent solution which is neutral to the set of all representative apportionments?

3. Existence of representative apportionments We begin our presentation of results with three propositions dealing with the existence of representative apportionments. The first one, which is proved in Laffond and Laine´ (1996) is the existence of profiles admitting no such apportionment:

44

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

Theorem 1. There exists a preference profile [s][P( N) such that GR ( N,s)5[. However, the proof presented in the reference above involves few voters and a very large set of candidates. The next theorem states that the same inexistence problem may arise even if the ratio candidates / voters is less than one: Theorem 2. There exists a profile [s][P( N) such that u Xu /u Nu#7 /9 and GR ( N,s)5[. Proof. Let N5h1,...,9j and X5h1,...,7j and let [s] be such that: • ;i [N, 1s i 2⇔i [N95h1,...,5j • ;i [N9, ;m[X2h1,2j, ms i 2⇔i5m22 • ;i [(N2N9), ;m[X2h1,2j, ms i 2 (All other majority pairwise comparisons do not matter.) It is obvious to check that T(s) is such that 2 is a Condorcet loser. Now let F 5hT 1 ,T 2 ,T 3 j be the set of sub-tournaments on X associated with any 3-apportionment A5hN1 ,N2 ,N3 j of N, where each constituency involves 3 voters. We claim that A is not representative. Indeed, suppose that A[ GR (N,s) and w.l.g. that 1T 1 2 and 1T 2 2. Since ;m±1,2, mT(s)2, it follows that ;m±1,2, m22[(N1 N9u52. Let i 0 [N1 and m 0 5i 0 12. Since i 0 is the only individual in N1 who prefers m 0 to 2, then 2T 1 m 0 . Furthermore, every individual in N2 >N9 prefers m 0 to 2, hence 2T 2 m 0 .Thus 'm 0 [ A2 h1,2j such that 2T 1 m 0 and 2T 2 m 0 , hence 2 TA (s)m 0 , which contradicts the representativeness of A. h Theorem 2 points out a significant difference between the dichotomous and the general case: in the former case, there always exist a district map which yields agreement with direct democracy, whereas in the latter case, maybe no district map yields a social preference relation that coincides with overall majority preferences. An essential ingredient in the proof above is the existence of majority dominations with tiny margins. What about the possibility to design representative apportionments when the overall tournament involves strong majorities, i.e. widespread social agreements? Suppose that n5Km, where K [h3,n21j denotes the (odd) number of constituencies (hence allowing for a perfect apportionment). Moreover, suppose that a majority of voters prefers some candidate y to some other one x. Then, in order for x to defeat y in a representational system, it must be the case that x is preferred to y by at least 0.25(K 11)(m11) voters (this is a necessary requirement for x to get a majority of votes against y in a majority of constituencies). It follows that the minimal proportion q of voters supporting x against y is [4Km] 21 [Km1K 1m11]; since q converges to 0.25 as K and m both go to `, it follows that no reversal of a majority preference can prevail in representational systems when the preference profile is such that all majority margins are larger than 75%. The next theorem generalizes this point to the case of non necessarily perfect apportionments:

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

45

Theorem 3. ;a$0.75, ;[s][P( N) such that T(s)[D(a), GR ( N,s)5G( N). Proof. Let A5hN1 ,...,N2k11 j be a K-apportionment of N where n k [h2p11,2p21j, 1#k#K. Let for any (x,y)[X 2 n x (resp. n y )5uhi [N: xs i yju(resp. n y 5uhi [N: ys i xju). Now suppose that xT(s)y (i.e. n x .n y ) and that yTA (s)x. This implies that n y $pb 2 1 ( p11)b 1 , where b 2 5uhh[h1,...,2k11j: uNh u52p21 and yT h (s)xju and b 1 5uhh[ h1,...,2k11j: uNh u52p11 and yT h (s)xju, and with the condition b 2 1 b 1 $(k11). One then has: • n y $p( b 2 1 b 1 )1 b 1 $p(k11)1 b 1 • n#(2p21)(2k112 b 1 )1(2p11)b 1 It follows that 4n y 2n$2p12k1112b 1 .0, hence that n y /n.0.25, a contradiction. h This result provides an interesting restriction on the set of profiles which ensures that majority preferences will not be biased through the representation process. It simply states that ‘popular willingness’ has to be strong enough. An immediate corollary of Theorem 3 is the existence of at least one non-representative apportionment when at least one majority margin is less than 75% (as long as the number of constituencies as well as the size of the electorate are large enough). In fact, things may become even worse: indeed, we now prove that, as long as some pairwise majority margin is lower than 0.75, there exists at least one profile for which no representative apportionment exists.8 Theorem 4. ;e.0, there exists [s][P( N) such that T(s)[D (0.752e) and GR ( N,s )5[. Proof. Let X5hw#N:uwu5mj, where 0,m#n. Let P be a complete linear order on X. For any i [N, i’s preferences on X are defined as follows: let (w,w9)[X 2 , with w±w9; then 1. 2. 3. 4.

if if if if

i [[w>w9], ws i w9⇔wPw9 i [[w2w9], w9s i w i [[w92w], ws i w9 i [N2[w
It follows by definition that ;w,w9[X such that wPw9, uhi [N: ws i w9ju5uw9u5m. Thus, if m.0.5n, T(s) coincides with P. We denote by P 2 the reverse order of P. Let assume that n is such that 'A5hN1 ,...,N2k 11 j[ G (N) such that n h 52p11, 1#h#2k11. The proof is organized in three steps: 8

It should be obvious that this result is not implied by Theorem 3: indeed, it is impossible to build a profile by considering mutually independent pairwise comparisons of candidates.

46

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

Step 1. Let h[h1,...,2k11j and w,w9[X. Let w h (resp. w9 h )5(w>Nh ) [resp. (w9>Nh )]. We claim that the preference profile ensures the following four simple statements: 1. If uw h u$( p11), uw9 h u$( p11) and wPw9, then wT h w9: indeed, i [w h9 ⇒ws i w9 (if i [w h >w h9 , this follows from Point 1 and wPw9, whereas if i [(w h 2w h9 ), this follows from Point 3) and thus it follows that at least ( p11) individuals in Nh prefer w to w9. 2. If uw h u$( p11), uw 9h u,( p11) and w9Pw, then w9T h w: note first that i [w h ⇒w9s i w: indeed, i [(w h 2w h9 )⇒w9s i w from Point 2, and i [w h >w h9 ⇒w9s i w from Point 1 and w9Pw. Then uw h u$( p11) implies that more than ( p11) individuals in Nh prefer w9 to w. 3. If uw h9 u,( p11) and wPw9, then w9T h w: one has i [ ⁄ w 9h ⇒w9s i w: indeed, i [(w h 2 w h9 )⇒w9s i w from Point 2, and i [[Nh 2(w h
<

k

hi 1 ,...,i ( 2p11 ) kjj5 h51 Nh , and where V 5hi ( 2p11)k 11 ,...,i m j is allocated among the remaining constituencies of A in such a way that ;h[hk11,...,2k11j, uNh > V u#p. It is obvious to check that uhh[h1,...,2k11j: uw 9h u$( p11)ju,(k11), which implies that w9TA (s)w*. Hence there is no representative apportionment. Step 3. ;e .0, N can be chosen such that T(s)[ D(0.752 e ) and GR (N,s)5[. Proof. Let m5(2p11)k1p(k11). It is straightforward to check that ;k, p$0, m /n, 0.75. The fact that lim k 5p→` [m /n]50.75 ends the proof of Theorem 4. h

4. Sensitivity of tournament solutions to representation

4.1. Representative systems under one-shot method We now investigate the sensitivity of tournament solution to apportionment when the final choice is made through the one-shot method. The existence of a representative apportionment ensures that direct and indirect democratic choices coincide. However, as seen above, there may exist no representative apportionment for some preference profile. Nevertheless, it might well be the case that some solution concept S may be nonsensitive to a non-representative apportionment. The next theorem states that this is not the case for the Uncovered Set:

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

47

Theorem 5. There exists a profile [s][P( N) such that u Xu /u Nu#7 /9, and ; A [G( N), UC[ T(s)]± UC[ TA (s)]. Proof. Let N5h1,...,9j and X5h1,...,7j and let [s] be defined by (voters’ names appear in the first row, and alternatives are listed in decreasing preference order): 1

2

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

1 a b 2 3 4 5

2 a b 4 5 3 1

a 3 b 1 5 4 2

a 4 b 5 2 3 1

a 5 b 1 3 2 4

3 5 1 4 2 b a

4 2 5 1 3 b a

1 5 3 2 4 b a

2 4 3 1 5 b a

It is easily checked that T(s) (hereafter denoted by T ) is such that 1 T 2,4,a,b, 2 T 3,4,a,b, 3 T 1,4,a,b, 4 T 5,b, 5 T 1,2,3,b, and a T 3,4,5,b. Thus b is a Condorcet loser, and it is easily checked that UC(T )5ha,1,2,3,4,5j. Let A5(Np ) h p51,2,3j be a 3-apportionment of N and let S 5[T p (s)] p51,2,3 be the associated set of tournaments on X. It follows from Theorem 2 that GR (N,s)5[. The proof is organized according to the following strategy: since no representative apportionment exists, '(x,y)[X 2 such that xTy and yTA (s)x; 9 each step of the proof is devoted to a specific set of (x,y)-type pairs of candidates. Step 1. y5b, x[h1,...,5j. Case 1. x51. It follows that one may assume w.l.g. that voters 2,3,4 and 5 form majorities in both N1 and N2 , and that either a is a Condorcet winner in TA or 2 TA a TA 1,3,4,5,b. In the former case, UC(TA )5haj±UC(T ). In the later case, UC(T )5UC(TA )⇒1,3,4,5 TA 2. Since hi [N: 4s i 2j5h3,4,6,7j, and hi [N: 3s i 2j5h3,5,6,8j, it is obviously seen that 4 TA 2⇔2 TA 3, hence either 3[ ⁄ UC(TA ), or 4[ ⁄ UC(TA ). Case 2. x52. Voters 1,3,4 and 5 form a majority in N1 and A in N2 , which implies that either a is a Condorcet winner in TA or 1 TA a TA 2,3,4,5,b. As above, UC(T )5UC(TA )⇒the later case prevails, and 2,3,4,5 TA 1 [condition (*)]. Since hi [N: 4s i 1j5h2,4,7,9j, one has to consider the following possible sub-cases:

9

To make notations simple, TA (s) and (T p (s)) p 51,2,3 will be respectively written TA and (T p ) p 51,2,3 .

48

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

Case 2.1. h2,4j,N1 and h7,9j,N2 : it must be the case that N1 is either h1,2,4j or h2,3,4j, or h2,4,5j. N1 5h1,2,4j and h1,3,4,5j have a majority in N1 and N2 imply with (*) that A5hN1 ,N2 ,N3 j[h(1,2,4),(6,7,9),(3,5,8)jUC(TA )5[. Moreover, N1 5h2,3,4j, (*), 3 TA 1 and b TA 2⇒ A5 h(2,3,4),(7,6,9),(1,5,8)j⇒4 TA 2,3,5⇒h2,3,5j>UC(TA )5[. Finally, the reader may easily check that N1 5h2,4,5j, 5 TA 1 and b TA 2⇒ A5h(2,4,5),(7,6,9),(1,3,8)j⇒4 TA 3,5, whereas 2 TA 3 TA 5 TA 2 and 2 TA 4⇒3[ ⁄ UC(TA ), hence UC(TA )±UC(T ). Case 2.2. h2,7j,N1 and h4,9j,N2 : b TA 2⇒N2 [h1,4,9jUC(TA )5 [. Moreover, if N2 5h3,4,9j, then b TA 2, 5 TA 1 and 3 TA 1 are mutually incompatible. Finally, if N2 5h4,5,9j, then b TA 2 and (*)⇒ A5hN1 ,N2 ,N3 j[h(2,6,7),(4,5,9),(1,3,8)j< h(2,7,8),(4,5,9),(1,3,6)j. In both cases, one get 2,4,5 TA 3, hence 3[ ⁄ UC(TA ). Case 2.3. h2,9j,N1 and h4,7j,N2 : b TA 2⇒N2 [h1,4,7jhi [N: 1s i 2j5h2,4,7,9j5[. Thus 1 TA 4 and thus 4[ ⁄ UC(TA ). Finally, suppose that 2 TA 1. Similarly, it must be the case that 3,4,5 TA 2. But this is impossible since hi [N: 2s i 1j5h2,4,7,9j>hi [N: 3s i 2j5 h3,5,6,8j5[. Thus, 3[ ⁄ UC(TA ). This proves that if x53, UC(T )±UC(TA ). The reader may check that if x[h4,5j, the same argument applies. This concludes the proof of Step 1. Step 2. y5b, x5a. This implies that voters 6,7,8 and 9 form a majority in two constituencies. It follows that a is a Condorcet loser in TA , hence a[ ⁄ UC(TA ), thus UC(TA )±UC(T ). Step 3. x5a, y[h3,4,5j. This implies that voters 6,7,8 and 9 form a majority in two constituencies. Hence we get the same conclusion as in Step 2.

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

49

Step 4. y5a, x[h1,2j. Suppose first that a TA 1. It follows from [s] that voters 2,3,4 and 5 form a majority in two constituencies. But this implies that b TA 1, and thus UC(TA )±UC(T ) from Step 1. Finally, if a TA 2, voters 1,3,4 and (form a majority in two constituencies, which implies that b TA 2, hence again UC(TA )±UC(T ) from Step 1. This concludes the proof. h When no restriction bear upon the ratio between the number of voters and the number of candidates, things may become even worse: it is possible to exhibit a preference profile such that, for any Condorcet-consistent tournament solution, direct and representative voting systems always leads to mutually disjoint sets of winners. Theorem 6. No Condorcet-consistent tournament solution S is weakly neutral to apportionment. Proof. Consider the preference profile [s] defined in the proof of Theorem 4. Let A5hN1 ,...,N2k 11 j[ G (N). Let Xh 1 5hw[X: uw h u,( p11)j, and Xh 2 5(X2Xh 1 ). It follows from the three assertions proved in Step 2 that ;h[h1,...,2k11j, T h (s) is a linear order on X defined by: • ;w,w9[Xh 1 , wT h (s)w9⇔wP 2 w9 • ;w,w9[Xh 2 , wT h (s)w9⇔wPw9 • ;w[Xh 1 , ;w9[Xh 2 , wT h (s)w9. Let us examine the tournament among representatives TA (s). For w,w9[X, define a, b, c and resp. by: • • • •

a5uhh[h1,...,2k11j: b5uhh[h1,...,2k11j: c5uhh[h1,...,2k11j: d5uhh[h1,...,2k11j:

w[Xh 2 w[Xh 2 w[Xh 1 w[Xh 1

and and and and

w9[Xh 2 ju w9[Xh 1 ju w9[Xh 2 ju w9[Xh 1 ju.

Then TA (s) will behave according to the relative values of a, b, c and d. This leads to the following possible cases: Case 1. (b2c).ua2du. This implies that wTA (s)w9. But (b2c).(a2d)⇔uhh[ h1,...,2k11j: w[Xh 1 ju$k11 and (b2c).(d2a)⇔uhh[h1,...,2k11j: w9[Xh 2 ju$k11. Case 2. (a2d).uc2bu. Then wTA (s)w9⇔wPw9. Moreover (a2d).(c2b)⇔uhh[ h1,...,2k11j: w9[Xh 2 ju$k11 and (a2d).(b2c)⇔uhh[h1,...,2k11j: w[Xh 2 ju$k11. 2

Case 3. (d2a).uc2bu. Then wTA (s)w9⇔wP w9. Moreover (d2a).(c2b)⇔uhh[ h1,...,2k11j: w[Xh 1 ju$k11 and (a2d).(b2c)⇔uhh[h1,...,2k11j: w9[Xh 1 ju$k11.

50

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

Case 4. (c2b).ua2du. We get w9TA (s)w. Moreover (c2b).(a2d)⇔uhh[h1,...,2k1 1j: w9[Xh 1 ju$k11 and (a2d).(b2c)⇔uhh[h1,...,2k11j: w[Xh 2 ju$k11. Define for A the set XA 1 (resp. XA 2) by XA 1 5hw[X: uhh[h1,...,2k11j: w9[Xh 1 ju$ k11j (resp. XA 2 5X2XA 1 ). We deduce from the four cases above that TA (s) is the linear order defined on X by: • ;w,w9[XA 1 , wTA (s) w9⇔wP 2 w9 • ;w,w9[XA 2 , wTA (s) w9⇔wPw9 • ;w[XA 1 , ;w9[XA 2 , wTA (s)w9. Finally, for any apportionment A, any Condorcet-consistent solution S will select from TA (s) as unique winner the top-element of XA 1 for P 2 , whereas S[T(s)] is clearly reduced to the top-element of X for P. The theorem follows from the fact that ;A[ G (N), XA 1 ±[. h

4.2. Representative system under the sequential choice method We turn now to the comparison between the direct system and the representative system based on the sequential choice method. The next result points out that the same negative result prevails as for the one-shot method: Theorem 7. No Condorcet-consistent solution S is weakly sequentially neutral to apportionment. Proof. Consider again the profile introduced in the proof of Theorem 4. It is shown in the proof of Theorem 4 that ;A5hNk , 1#h#2k11j, T h (s) is a linear order on X defined by: • ;w,w9[Xh 1 , wT h (s)w9⇔wP 2 w9 • ;w,w9[Xh 2 , wT h (s)w9⇔wPw9 • ;w[Xh 1 , ;w9[Xh 2 , wT h (s)w9 where Xh 1 5hw[X: uw h u,( p11)j, and Xh 2 5(X2Xh 1 ). Let x h 1 and x*, respectively, denote the Condorcet winner of T h (s) and of T(s). Since T(s) coincides with P, it follows that ;h51,...,2k11, [ < h x h 1 ]>hx*j5[. Hence, for any Condorcet-consistent solution S, S[T(s)]5hx*j>[S(TA (s) / < 1#h#2k11 x h 1 ]5[ h. This result again rests heavily upon the non-existence of some representative apportionment. We may expect such apportionment to play the same role for the one-shot and the sequential choice methods. The next theorem shows that this conjecture is false, despite the very restrictive nature of the representativeness requirement:

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

51

Theorem 8. There exists a profile [s][P( N) such that G( N)5GR ( N,s) and, for any Condorcet consistent solution S finer than UC, [ S( T(s))]>[ S( TA (s) / < 1# k # K S( Tk (s)))]5[ ; Ah Nk ,1# k # Kj. Proof. See Laffond and Laine´ (1996). We just sketch the proof here. It involves a slight modification of the profile introduced in the proof of Theorem 4: let X5hw,N: uwu52p21j and P be a linear order on X; voter i’s preferences over a pair hw,w9j are now defined by: • if i [[w>w9], ws i w9⇔w9Pw • if i [[w2w9], ws i w9 • if i [N2[ww9u.p. Thus uhk: w9T k (s)wju#1 (since constituencies are mutually disjoint). This implies that A is representative. Now suppose that w*[ ⁄ A. Let w[X be s.t. w*T 1 (s)w. We have from [s] that uN1 2wu.0.5uN1 u. Moreover, ;i [(N1 2w), N1 s i w. Since N1 s i w*;i [N1 , we get that N1 →w* in T k (s), hence w*[ ⁄ UC[T 1 (s)]. In the case where w*[ A, it is left to the reader to prove that w**→w* in all T k (s), where w** is the second top element of X for P. Thus w*[ ⁄ < 1#k #KUC[T k (s)]. Hence w*[ ⁄ UC. h

<

1#k #K

S[T k (s)] for any S ,

This result may be given the following statistical-type interpretation, dealing with the accuracy of predictions about the election results: suppose that the prevailing system in a society N with (2m11)(2k11) voters is direct democracy, and that the set of candidates is X5hw,N: uwu52p21j; therefore, the actual voting outcome is given by S[T(s)]; moreover, suppose that T(s) has a Condorcet winner w*. Now, consider an opinion research institute which tries to forecast the election outcome, using a sample Nh of size 2k11. The survey outcome is then given by S[T k (s)]. The above proof defines a profile for which this outcome announce that, for any possible sampling design, w* will be defeated. Our last result deals with the sensitivity of Condorcet-consistent solutions to the choice of a specific apportionment. It states that any such solution is sensitive to the set of representative apportionments. More precisely, the profile described in the proof of the next theorem allows for two representative apportionments leading to mutually disjoint sets of winners: Theorem 9. No Condorcet consistent solution S is weakly non-sensitive to GR ( N,s). Proof. Consider the profile defined in the proof of Theorem 8 and assume that N5h1,...,9j. It is already seen that G (N)5 GR (N,s). Let A5hN1 ,N2 ,N3 j[ G (N). Define

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

52

2 for k51,2,3 the sets X 1 by Xk 2 5hw[X: uw>Nk u$2j and Xk 2 5(X2Xk 2). k and Xk Using the same arguments as in the proof of Theorem 6, one get that T k has w *k as Condorcet winner, where w k* is the worst element of Xk 2 for P. Now suppose that P is such that w 1 5h1,2,3jPw 2 5h4,5,6jPw 3 5h7,8,9jPw 4 5h1,4,7j Pw 5 5h2,5,8j P 2 w 6 5 h3,6,9j P 2 w ;w±w h , h51,...,6. Let A and A9 be the apportionments, respectively defined by A5hN1 ,N2 ,N3 j5hw 1 ,w 2 ,w 3 j and A95hN 19 ,N 29 ,N 39 j5hw 4 ,w 5 ,w 6 j. It fol-

lows that

<

<

h 51,2,3

S(T h )5hw 1 ,w 2 ,w 3 j, whereas

<

h51,2,3

S(T h9 )5hw 4 ,w 5 ,w 6 j. Thus

S(TA / k51,2,3 S(T k )5[. It is left to the reader to check that the proof is easily generalized to any number n of voters. h

5. Concluding comments This paper may be conceived as an attempt to enlarge the set of axioms for tournament solution concepts with an additional one having a positive flavor, for most collective decision procedures are actually of sequential nature. It appears that, unless when there is a widespread agreement on pairwise comparisons between candidates, there is no hope for a sincere political body to design apportionments of the electorate without bearing the risk to be accused of gerrymandering. Indeed, sensitivity to the drawing of electoral districts appears to be an intrinsic feature of a representational system based on the majority rule. Many routes for further research may be followed. One is to plug a representative democratic setting into already studied models of political competition. We guess that a better understanding of the way political parties can strategically use the apportionment mechanism is still to be achieved, and would be of great interest to improve the positive theory of political institutions. A first set of results is given in Laffond and Laine´ (1996). More generally, all results obtained in voting game theory could be reexamined within our setting. This is the topic of an ongoing research.

Acknowledgements The helpful comments of two anonymous referees are gratefully acknowledged. A first version of this paper was written while the second author was visiting the Economics Department of Keele University. The authors thank the staff of this department, and especially Richard Cornes, Peter Lawrence and Gauthier Lanot for valuable discussions.

References Murakami, Y., 1966. Formal structure of majority decision. Econometrica 34, 709–718. Fishburn, P.C., 1971. The theory of representative decision. Econometrica 39, 273–284. Fine, K., 1972. Some necessary and sufficient conditions for representative decision on two alternatives. Econometrica 40, 1083–1090.

G. Laffond, J. Laine´ / Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (2000) 35 – 53

53

May, K.O., 1952. A set of independent, necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica 20, 680–684. Balinsky, M.L., Young, H.P., 1975. The quota method for apportionment. American Mathematical Monthly 82, 701–730. Balinsky, M.L., Young, H.P., 1982. Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote, Yale University Press, New Haven. Nurmi, H., 1998. Voting paradoxes and referenda. Social Choice and Welfare 15, 333–350. Nurmi, H., 1997. Referendum design: An exercise in applied social choice theory. Scandinavian Political Studies 20, 33–52. Ostrogorski, M., 1903. La Democratie et l’Organisation des Partis Politiques, 2 vols., Calmann-Levy, Paris. Anscombe, G.E.M., 1976. On frustration of the majority by fulfilment of the majority’s will. Analysis 36, 161–168. Daudt, H., Rae, D., 1976. The Ostrogorski paradox: A peculiarity of compound majority decision. European Journal of Political Research 4, 391–398. Deb, R., Kelsey, D., 1987. On constructing a generalized Ostrogorski paradox: Necessary and sufficient conditions. Mathematical Social Sciences 14, 161–174. Nermuth, M., 1992. Two-stage aggregation: The Ostrogorski paradox and related phenomena. Social Choice and Welfare 9, 99–116. Moulin, H., 1986. Choosing from a tournament. Social Choice and Welfare 2, 271–291. Dutta, B., 1988. Covering sets and a new Condorcet choice correspondence. Journal of Economic Theory 44, 63–80. Schwartz, T., 1990. Cyclic tournaments and cooperative majority voting: A solution. Social Choice and Welfare 7, 19–29. Laffond, G., Laslier, J.F., Lebreton, M., 1995. Condorcet choice correspondences: A set-theoretical comparison. Mathematical Social Sciences 30, 25–35. ´ J., Laslier, J.F., 1996. Composition-consistent tournament solutions and social choice Laffond, G., Laine, functions. Social Choice and Welfare 13, 75–93. Banks, J.S., 1985. Sophisticated voting outcomes and agenda control. Social Choice and Welfare 2, 295–306. Fisher, D.C., Ryan, J., 1992. Optimal strategies for a generalized ‘scissors, paper and stone’ game. American Mathematical Monthly 19, 935–942. Fisher, D.C., Ryan, J., 1995. Tournament games and positive tournaments. Journal of Graph Theory 19, 217–236. Fisher, D.C., Ryan, J., 1995. Condorcet voting and tournament games. Linear Algebra and its Applications 217, 87–100. Laffond, G., Laslier, J.F., Lebreton, M., 1993. The bipartisan set of a tournament game. Games and Economic Behavior 5, 182–220. Laffond, G., Laslier, J.F., Lebreton, M., 1994. Social choice mediators. American Economic Review 84, 448–453. Laslier, J.F., 1997. Tournament Solutions and Majority Voting, Springer Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York. Wagner, C., 1983. Anscombe’s paradox and the rule of three-fourth. Theory and Decision 15, 303–308. Wagner, C., 1984. Avoiding Anscombe’s paradox. Theory and Decision 16, 233–238. Smith, J.H., 1973. Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41, 1027–1041. Young, H.P., 1975. Social choice scoring functions. SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics 28, 824–838. MacGarvey, D.C., 1953. A theorem on the construction of voting paradoxes. Econometrica 21, 608–610. Miller, N.R., 1977. Graph-theoretical approaches to the theory of voting. American Journal of Political Science 21, 769–803. Miller, N.R., 1980. A new solution set for tournament and majority voting: Further graph-theoretical approaches to the theory of voting. American Journal of Political Science 24, 68–96. Shepsle, K., Weingast, B., 1982. Uncovered sets and sophisticated voting outcomes with applications for agenda institutions. American Journal of Political Science 28, 49–74. ´ J., 1994. Weak covering relations. Theory and Decision 37, 245–265. Laffond, G., Laine, ´ J., 1996. Tournament choice and representative democracy, CNAM Working Paper. Laffond, G., Laine,