Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects Go¨ran Hermere´n, Lund University, Lund, Sweden Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Abs...

127KB Sizes 1 Downloads 84 Views

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects Go¨ran Hermere´n, Lund University, Lund, Sweden Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Abstract After an initial clarification of the notion of the risk, a brief discussion of the distinction between testing and screening, and of the difficulties of defining ‘genetic information’ in a precise way follows an overview of public concerns raised by genetic testing and screening. Next section reviews various types of ethical issues in this context. The challenges are not the same for all types and purposes of such methods. The following sections therefore discuss issues raised by preimplantation diagnosis, prenatal diagnosis, prenatal and neonatal screening, presymptomatic testing, testing at the workplace and forensic uses of genetic tests. Finally some future concerns are outlined briefly.

The Human Genome Organization project has increased enormously the possibilities to predict disability or disease either for an individual or for his or her offspring. Information obtained from genetic testing raises ethical and legal issues that have been debated for several decades. New issues are emerging due to rapid advances in molecular genetics. From an ethical point of view, risk screening, genetic testing, and diagnosis belong to the most controversial and contested areas in contemporary medicine. The new genetics will have a profound impact on our self-images and on our understanding of the relations between environment and heritage. Conceptual, normative, and empirical issues are here intertwined in a complex way. To begin with, a preliminary clarification of the key concepts will be necessary. The expression ‘risk’ will here be taken to refer to an adverse or negative future event that is probable but not certain, for example, given a certain exposure. Any risk can then be analyzed in two components: the probability of occurrence of an event and the magnitude of its negativity (including kind, degree, duration, and timing) according to certain more or less explicitly stated norms and values. Risk assessment accordingly analyzes these two components, while risk management proposes strategies for handling the risk in ways that minimize the negativity and probability. However, risks involving probabilities are not the only the sort of risks that are relevant in this context. The expression ‘epistemic risk’ has been coined to refer to risks due to ignorance, and in particular due to ignorance of what we are ignorant about (e.g., Sahlin and Persson, 1994). This notion is particularly relevant to many clinical applications of molecular genetics, involving unknown factors. The ways in which these risks are communicated will then be important from an ethical point of view. Testing should be distinguished from screening. Harper has proposed the following definition: “Genetic testing is the analysis of a specific gene, its product or function, or other DNA and chromosome analysis, to detect or exclude an alteration likely to be associated with a genetic disorder” (Harper and Clarke, 1997). Testing refers to procedures performed at the request of individuals or families, and should always be voluntary. This holds also for genetic testing of members of families known to be at high risk, such as the siblings of persons with cystic fibrosis (Wertz and Fletcher, 1989). ‘Screening,’ however, implies application to large population groups, to entire populations or subsets of populations (e.g., pregnant women, newborns, or job applicants). Screening

698

is not performed at the request of individuals or families but rather based on policy or public health decisions. It may be mandatory or voluntary. Both the expressions ‘genetic information’ and ‘genetic disorder’ are vague and ambiguous concepts (Zimmern, 1999). The same holds for the key concepts of health, disease, and illness. The advances in molecular and clinical genetics may profoundly change our understanding of the latter concepts. They may have an impact on health care policy, on the patient– physician relationship as well as the way in which access to care is allocated (Murray et al., 1996). Genetic information differs from other private information in that it reveals information not only about a particular individual but also about that individual’s blood relatives. Genetic test results may also provide information about population groups. Moreover, genetic information can be obtained from any cell in a person’s body, not just by examining, for example, particular malfunctioning organs or tissues. The concept of genetic information is difficult to define and delimit in a clear and uncontroversial way. Just by asking for the age of a person’s parents and grandparents, genetic information in a certain sense can be obtained. The necessary and sufficient conditions for a disease or disorder to be ‘genetic’ or ’hereditary’ are far from clear. If the expressions ‘genetic information’ and ‘genetic disorder’ are to appear in legislative texts, they have to be made precise. There are many kinds of genetic disorders, including (1) chromosome changes, like trisomy 21 or Down’s syndrome, (2) monogenetic disorders which depend on a mutation in one gene, like Huntington’s chorea, and (3) polygenetic disorders like diabetes which are due to mutations in several genes in combination with environmental factors. They are complex and multifactorial. These distinctions are important for several reasons. What holds for monogenetic diseases concerning genetic determinism cannot be generalized to genetic disorders of other kinds. Thus, presymptomatic testing can be done for disorders in group (2) but rarely and with much less certainty, if at all, for those in group (3).

Public Concerns Genetic testing may be beneficial in those cases where early detection makes a difference, for example, makes it possible to

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 20

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.31032-7

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

prevent or cure the disease. The validity and the reliability of the test methods will then be of crucial importance. The background of many national screening programs, like the one launched in Ontario, Canada, in 1999, to detect risk of hereditary breast, ovarian, and colon cancers is that early detection can lead to medical interventions and surveillance. This can significantly reduce the risk of developing the disease and hence be cost-effective. The concern expressed over genetic testing and screening, however, is that it may threaten privacy and civil rights and be the basis of genetic discrimination or stigmatization of individuals as well as of groups. Moreover, it has been feared that widespread use of genetic testing will help to foster intolerance of people with genetic variations. It may be difficult, too, if not impossible, for people with certain inherited disorders to obtain a life insurance. Finally, people may feel a pressure to be tested, as a result of cost–benefit analysis. In general, of course, the negative consequences of testing people and disclosing information about their test results to blood relatives will have to be weighed against the benefits of this, if any, for those concerned. However, this weighing operation is far from simple. Direct-to-consumer testing (DTC) has emerged as an increasingly controversial issue. Under what conditions can it be justified? What could and should be done about different forms of DTC? Consumer protection is obviously a relevant concern. But internet sales are difficult to regulate. Hogarth et al., 2008 provide an overview of the current landscape for the developing market for DTC genetic testing, and reviews the legal, ethical, and policy issues raised by this testing. The need to be cautious when considering and interpreting such testing has been stressed (Dandara et al., 2013). The reason is that the clinical validity and utility of genetic tests for many complex multifactorial disorders is questionable. Recommendations to protect consumers and healthcare providers are proposed by these authors. Patrinos et al. (2013) discuss a variant of the DTC business model, where private molecular genetic testing services are offered for sale over the counter by pharmacies, and the authors stress the lack of awareness on the part of both the patients and the general public with respect to the potential benefits and risks of the tests offered. Guidelines for genetic testing and screening have been proposed in the attempt to maximize the beneficial consequences and minimize the adverse ones (by e.g., the Nuffield Council on Bioethics (1993); the Danish Council of Ethics (1993); UNESCO (1997); the Council of Europe (1996, 2008)). These guidelines include recommendations concerning genetic counseling, informed consent, disclosure to individuals and family members, confidentiality, employment, insurance, as well as public policy. The commercial availability of genetic test kits raises both operational and ethical issues, dealt within the principles and recommendations suggested by National Institutes of Health (1997). This report discusses the validity of genetic testing, deals with genetic counseling and the informed consent process, as well as recommendations on quality assurance measures for laboratories performing genetic tests and the need for a national body with the authority to review genetic testing procedures. The future development, indicated by the increased transition from chance to choice (Buchanan et al., 2000), includes

699

a growing multitude of choices, possibilities to test earlier, and without procedure-related risks. This raises many ethical issues, not only about who will get access to the new technologies.

Ethical Issues The ethical issues include the risk for potential harm by false positives and false negative, and by invasive procedures, the risks for genetic discrimination, how to promote and protect important values like autonomy (respect for persons), privacy, confidentiality, justice and fair access, and more generally how to estimate, weight and balance benefits and harms. There has to be a reasonable proportion between risks and benefits, but how this is to be understood more precisely is not clear (Hermerén, 2012).

Harms and Benefits Invasive procedures can be harmful, e.g., by causing miscarriage. But harm can also be created in other ways. The accuracy of the tests – their validity and reliability – and the predictive value of the test or the screening method is clearly an important issue in this context. To estimate the predictive value, one has to be able to compute the number of false positives (who are worried unnecessarily) and false negatives (who are lulled into false security) as well as to know about the prevalence of the genetic disorder.

Autonomy It has often been recommended that genetic information in health care should be acquired and used “in a manner that respects the autonomy of individuals” (Institute of Medicine, 1994), but it has proved hard to explain the precise meaning of this in a noncontroversial way. The autonomy of what individuals should be respected? Sometimes respecting the autonomy of one individual may conflict with respecting the autonomy of another. The principle of reproductive autonomy is problematic in the context of prenatal testing, because of possible interference with the supposed rights of the unborn child (Haker, 2008). Traditional ways to promote and protect autonomy include nondirective counseling and informed consent. A general problem raised by all forms of genetic testing and screening is, first, how to give nondirective information, that is, information that makes autonomous decisions possible by individuals and couples, and then to obtain consent in a way that avoids exercise of pressure. Why is nondirectiveness an important goal? In brief, the reasons are the value of autonomy and the importance for geneticists to dissociate themselves from the dark history of genetics, from abuse of genetics for eugenic purposes. But nondirectiveness in practice is not uncomplicated, and the goal is also controversial. Hardly surprising, there is an ongoing debate on the process of genetic counseling beyond nondirectiveness (Clarke, 1994; Harper and Clarke, 1997). Particular problems are raised by the testing of individuals or groups with reduced autonomy, like children, demented people, or immigrants who do not understand the language.

700

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

The testing of a healthy child could arise in at least three different contexts (Chadwick, 1998): predictive testing, to see if the child will develop a specific disease that runs in the family; carrier testing, to see if the child may be at risk of having an affected child; and a screening test unrelated to family history to identify children with increased susceptibility to some common disease such as diabetes or ischemic heart disease. Children are vulnerable and their parents therefore have to be involved in the decision procedure. But how? The nature of parental consent and the degree to which children are to be involved according to their maturity need close examination. If relatives are to be informed, who should do this? The geneticist, the hospital, or those already tested? And in what way? How many relatives should be informed? How closely related to the person asking to be tested (the index person) should the relatives be for the clinical geneticist to be responsible for informing them? Different consent models are available, each with their own pros and cons. One main alternative is called ‘opt in,’ which means that if you have not said yes, you have said no; another is called ‘opt out,’ which means that if you have not said no, you have said yes. The conditions under which any of these models may or must be used is an important ethical issue. Informed consent has traditionally been one of the basic principles in practical medical ethics. But the ambiguity of the term ‘informed consent’ has been stressed by Manson and O’Neill 2007. Moreover, new developments in genetic testing challenge this principle in its traditional form. It has, for instance, been suggested that opportunistic screening presents the most serious challenge to patient autonomy in this century, particularly in prostate-specific antigen screening, newborn screening and prenatal diagnosis of maternal blood tests for fetal anomalies (Davis, 2013). Recent developments in genomics technologies have paved the way for broad genome-wide testing for dozens of diseases at the same time. Bunnik et al. (2013a) have proposed a tiered-layered-staged model for informed consent in personal genome testing. It is suggested that this model for informed consent can help to overcome the ethical problems of information provision and informed consent in direct to consumer personal genome testing. Whole-genome sequencing and microarray based analyses also challenge the feasibility of providing adequate pretest information and achieving autonomous decision making. It has been argued that informed consent is a prerequisite but requires a new approach (Bunnik et al., 2013b). Preliminary and general directions for the testing offer and for the informed consent process are presented in their paper.

Privacy and The Right to Know The challenge to genetic privacy concerns the control of personal genetic information. Privacy has two dimensions, according to the Canadian Human Rights Commission (1992): protection from the intrusion of others and protection from one’s own secrets. Does this entail a right to genetic ignorance, a right not to know about one’s own or one’s relatives’ genetic risk profile? Is there a duty for geneticists or tested persons to disclose such information to those who might benefit from it?

If so, what is the basis of such rights and duties, and what are the consequences for the various people concerned of accepting or rejecting them? Opposite positions have been argued for by Rhodes (1998) and Takala and Hayry (2000). Several compromise positions have been put forward. Tested persons should be encouraged to share what they know about their genetic risk profile with their blood relatives, when this information would be of vital health interest to their relatives (Chadwick et al., 1997; Hermerén, 2000). The right to know your genetic parents has been a lively discussed issue in recent years. A central role in the debate has been the comparison between different situations. Some have argued that the right to know the identity of the gamete donor should be extended to naturally conceived children with misattributed paternity. Routine paternity testing at birth should therefore be carried out (Ravelingien and Pennings, 2013). Others have questioned the similarities between gamete donation and misattributed paternity and argued that they should be treated differently. Underlying this debate is the contested value of genetic relatedness, on which there are many different views.

Confidentiality of Genetic Information The confidentiality of the information needs to be protected against third party interests, including other family members, employers, and insurers. It has been suggested that genetic information should not be given to unrelated third parties, without the explicit and informed consent of the tested persons. In many countries, access to genetic information is regulated by law. The conditions or criteria under which medical confidentiality may or must be breached are bound to be controversial (Harper and Clarke, 1997). The practical problems raised by genetic testing also have to do with how to estimate and evaluate risks, communicate them in an understandable way, and decide which risks are acceptable and which are not. This includes the risk that a person will have an increased risk for a genetic disorder and the risk that the test result is not accurate. Communicating risks is obviously an important part of the genetic counseling process.

Justice and Fair Access Finally, there are issues of justice and fair access. The health care systems in most countries are under increasing economic pressure. Different ways of cutting costs, manage the care, and require copayment by patients have been introduced. If testing and screening is to be done on an equitable basis, it should not be available on the basis of such accidents as in which geographical region a person happens to be born. The ethical problems outlined above arise in somewhat different ways, according to the type and purpose of testing or screening. The challenges are not the same in all cases. In particular, certain forms of screening and presymptomatic testing for late onset genetic disorders present problems from an ethical point of view. Some of the most common types of genetic testing and screening will therefore be described below along with a brief indication of the particular ethical problems they raise.

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

Types of Testing and Screening Taking the chronological development of a person’s life as a point of departure, rather than the historical development of the various technologies, we may distinguish between methods used before implantation of the fertilized egg in uterus (preimplantation), before the individual is born (prenatal), when the individual is newborn (neonatal), after birth but before symptoms are visible (presymptomatic) or later to find out if the person or his or her future children are at risk to develop some hereditary disease (carrier). In addition to them, there are genetic tests and screening methods for specific applications, for instance, in workplaces (susceptibility) or in potentially legal cases (forensic).

Preimplantation Diagnosis Preimplantation diagnosis means that the diagnosis is carried out before (in connection with in vitro fertilization) the preembryo is implanted in the woman’s uterus. If there were a history of sex-linked diseases in a family, it would then be possible to prevent a child with such a disease being born. Thus the resulting pregnancy could be normal and the woman would not have to abort the fetus at a later stage or give birth to a child with a very serious or lethal disease. Preimplantation diagnosis is becoming an established medical practice in many countries. The first serious ethical problem that arises is to whom these tests should be offered. Usually, they are limited to severe illnesses and to persons in specific ‘high risk’ groups. But both these criteria are value laden, and the indications may be narrowed down or widened. There are also considerable variations not only between lay people but also between geneticists over the severity of different genetic conditions (Chadwick, 1998). Preimplantation diagnosis at the beginning of the twentyfirst century is thus limited to sorting out fertilized eggs carrying genes associated with severe diseases for which there is no cure at present, like Huntington’s chorea and certain X-linked diseases. Concern has been expressed that the practice may be extended to diseases that are less serious (Shenfield, 1997). Obviously, there is a risk of a slippery slope in this area. Preimplantation diagnosis also, at least theoretically, opens up possibilities for a shift of power from the woman to the geneticist, as well as for cloning and manipulation of human pre-embryos that many people find too risky or simply ethically unacceptable. In many countries, manipulation of human pre-embryos is illegal. The technological development in this area is rapid. For instance, Harper and Harton 2010 describe the current use of array technology and make suggestions for future use of arrays in preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) and preimplantation genetic screening (PGS). They also discuss the steps that need to be taken if array-based testing is going to prove useful. Comprehensive techniques like microarray technology and whole genome sequencing have the potential to change the practice of PGD and PGS. Hens et al., 2013 describe an expert panel study of how to deal with the extra information these procedures yield, including which conditions to test for and who should have a final say on which embryo to select.

701

Prenatal Diagnosis Prenatal diagnosis can be regarded as a special case of presymptomatic testing. By prenatal diagnosis it is possible to discern whether a fetus is at risk for various disabilities or diseases. There are several methods for prenatal diagnosis. Some are visual – either noninvasive, like ultrasonography, or invasive, like embryoscopy or fetoscopy, which uses a camera on a needle inserted in the uterus to view the fetus. Other methods are based on the analysis of fetal tissues (like amniocentesis or chorionic villus sampling). By ultrasound tomography it is possible to create fetal images on a screen. The distinction between invasive and noninvasive methods is important. The former can do harm during the test procedure, e.g. by causing miscarriage. From that point of view various noninvasive techniques have emerged as very promising, provided that the problem of avoiding false positive and false negative test results can be dealt with adequately. The analysis of fetal DNA in the blood of the mother is one such method that has been gaining ground in recent years. There are several overviews and discussions of current applications of circulating fetal nucleic acids (cell-free fetal DNA) in genetic testing for different kinds of hereditary diseases, particularly in diagnosis of monogenic disorders (Ma et al., 2013). Genetic skin diseases are of varying severity and this raises issues of the responsibility of doctors and parents in the prenatal genetic testing. The complexity of the issues calls for guidelines about the best practice in this kind of testing. Allyse et al., 2013 have proposed an ethical framework for clinicians and companies providing noninvasive prenatal testing using cell-free fetal DNA or whole fetal cells as a basis for a set of best practices for the provision of noninvasive prenatal genetic testing. The recommendations include the amendment of current informed consent procedures. The authors strongly recommend that these tests should only be available through licensed medical providers and not directly to consumers. The indications of when prenatal diagnosis should be offered include advanced maternal age, a genetic history of abnormalities in the family, repeated miscarriages, or previous infants with birth defects. Then a prenatal diagnosis may be offered to provide information to couples about what they can expect. A normal result is found in most cases. If not, prenatal diagnosis may make it possible for them to adjust and may also influence the way in which the baby is delivered. There has been great concern about the risk of spontaneous abortion induced by the use of invasive methods like amniocentesis or chorionic villus sampling. This is a problem one does not have with ultrasonography and other noninvasive methods. On the other hand, ultrasonography may give information that is unexpected or not wanted, for example, that some organs or limbs are malformed. With other methods, too, one may make unexpected or unwanted discoveries, for example, that the social father is not the biological father. A well-known issue that continues to be controversial is how to deal with incidental findings in genetic testing. The new genetic technologies have made this challenge even more urgent. Incidental findings can range from identifying

702

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

increased risk for certain inherited diseases to revealing misattributed paternity. Should the tested person always be told? If not, what criteria could and should be used to single out the exceptions? Should incidental findings discovered with whole-genome sequencing or testing be sought and reported to ordering clinicians and to patients or their surrogates? Contradictory answers to this question have been argued for in a discussion of a statement by the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (Green et al., 2013; Friedman Ross, 2013). McGuire et al., 2013 also discuss the recommendations of the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics to seek and report pathogenic mutations for a short list of carefully chosen genes and conditions. The authors focus on the ethical framework for these recommendations. They argue that standards are needed, that patient autonomy – including the right not to know – should be respected, and that children and adults should be treated equally. All this serves to underline the necessity of careful counseling before the diagnosis, so that the woman or the couple knows what the test may show and how certain the result is. Informed consent is crucial, but the difficulties of nondirective counseling should not be underestimated. Other ethical issues raised by this type of diagnosis are concerned with how to preserve the confidentiality of the information obtained. Since prenatal diagnostics sometimes leads to abortion, it may be controversial in the eyes of some people for the same reasons that abortion is controversial. The impact of prenatal diagnosis on our views of people with handicap has also been a matter of concern.

Prenatal and Neonatal Screening Newborn screening involves the analysis of blood or tissue samples taken in early infancy in order to detect inherited diseases where early intervention can minimize or eliminate the risk of later serious health problems or premature death. In prenatal screening, conventional karyotyping is being replaced by genome-wide array-based techniques (A de Jong et al., 2011). In screening, a group of individuals is examined directly with DNA, RNA, or biochemical analysis to find those who will later in life have an increased risk of developing a particular genetic disorder. A good screening method is reliable and valid, with a minimum of false positives and false negatives. A well-known example of uncontroversial neonatal screening is screening for phenylketonuria (PKU), a genetic disease. The reason is that PKU, if undetected, can lead to serious mental retardation. Moreover, it can be discovered easily and prevented through early intervention. For many other conditions, such as cystic fibrosis and galactosemia, the benefits of early detection are more controversial. Screening programs for newborns also raise the issues of freedom of choice and informed consent by parents (Hermerén, 1999). Newborn screening raises several ethical issues, among them the nature of informed parental consent and how it is obtained, confidentiality and privacy, and the interests of third parties, as well as issues of justice such as equal access to testing and treatment. Moreover, it is clear that more research needs to be carried out on the psychological responses to newborn

screening, particularly when the health benefits are disputed (Harper and Clarke, 1997). Recent technological developments have made it possible to collect a huge amount of information about the genetic status of the fetus. However, this information is to some extent uncertain, its meaning is variable, and its relevance to the woman or the couple contested. It has been suggested that the ethical debate should focus on the clinical context and on the ends of prenatal screening and diagnostics (Schmitz, 2013). If that is done, the ethical debate would be able to provide a more comprehensive and useful analysis of the ethical challenges presented by in particular the new technologies. People with certain genetic disorders have had difficulties in getting a life insurance. In some countries the right of insurance companies to ask for genetic information has been regulated by law. In Norway, it is forbidden. In other countries – The Netherlands and Sweden, for instance – there has been a temporary voluntary moratorium during which the insurance companies will not ask for genetic information, provided that the life insurance asked for will not exceed a certain amount. This is still a very controversial area (Sandberg, 1996).

Presymptomatic Testing Individuals may be tested for monogenetic disorders (of which there are many though each is fairly rare) by DNA analysis before any symptoms are shown. If an early diagnosis is of value, because the disease can be prevented, presymptomatic testing is fairly uncontroversial. If the disorder cannot be prevented, the value of presymptomatic testing is more difficult to judge. This holds also in cases where there is a method of prevention, but it is nevertheless impossible to guarantee that the person tested positively will not get the disease (e.g., breast cancer). In addition to the obvious difficulty of informing people in such a way that they can make autonomous decisions, presymptomatic testing raises problems about how the information obtained from the tests should be handled, and who should have access to it. Likewise, it is controversial whether blood relatives should be contacted and who should contact them in that case (the person tested, the hospital, the clinic, the geneticist, etc.). Moreover, in many countries there is great concern about how to prevent certain external third parties, like employers or insurers, from getting access to information about the test result.

Carrier Screening Carrier screening identifies individuals with a gene or chromosome abnormality that may cause problems either for offspring or for the person screened. The testing of blood or tissue samples can indicate the existence of particular genetic trait changes in chromosomes or changes in DNA that are associated with inherited diseases in asymptomatic individuals. Carrier screening exists for sickle cell anemia, for Tay Sachs disease, as well as for cystic fibrosis, Duchenne muscular dystrophy, hemophilia, and Huntington’s chorea. Carriers have one normal copy of a gene and one copy that varies from the normal gene. Since one gene is normal, the carriers ordinarily do not exhibit symptoms of a genetic

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

disorder. A woman who is a carrier of an X-linked disease such as Duchenne muscular dystrophy or fragile X syndrome, has a variant gene on one of their two X (sex-determining) chromosomes. Her risk of transmitting the variant gene to each child can be estimated accurately. The purpose of carrier testing is to inform potential parents of their genetic risk profile so that they can make informed reproductive decisions. National screening programs are usually justified by cost–benefit analysis. The question is then which costs and whose costs are taken into account, and how the benefits are defined and evaluated. The importance of cultural differences as to what constitutes benefits, and how benefits are ranked, should not be underestimated. The right to autonomous choices is an important issue also in this area. Whether the choices open to people found to carry a disease gene are acceptable or not, may depend on their life plans, their ethical views, the laws of their country, as well as their culture and social customs. Before a carrier screening program is decided on and implemented, these questions need to be considered. In practice there may be subtle coercion, even if a carrier screening program is formally voluntary. Screening the subset of a population at risk rather than the entire population makes sense from a medical and economic point of view, but selecting target groups for such screening programs also creates ethical problems. For example, there have been in the past controversies over whether some screening programs in effect had a eugenic purpose, particularly when the diseases screened for are overrepresented in certain ethnic groups.

Testing in the Work Place Susceptibility screening can be used as a form of presymptomatic testing, but is also used to identify workers who may be susceptible to toxic or carcinogenic substances such as benzene in their workplace (Van Damme et al., 1997; Surralles et al., 1997; Jarvholm et al., 1999). This susceptibility may lead to occupational health problems and future severe disabilities. Van Damme et al. (1995) have proposed a conceptual model of the complex interactions between exposure, acquired and inherited susceptibility, and risk for disease. The validity of tests for determining genotype and phenotype and their relevance for the disease must be evaluated critically to provide an objective basis for ethical discussions. The acceptability of such tests is related to a number of issues which Van Damme et al. identify and discuss. Genetic testing of employees and job applicants is controversial. The first basic question concerning testing in the work place is simple – for whose sake is the test performed? Is the test performed in order to protect persons with increased (inherited) susceptibility to hazards at the workplace? Or is the test in the interest of the employer, so that the employer can avoid improving the working conditions and avoid hiring people who would be damaged by the work they do? Here it is essential to separate the situation of the job applicant from the situation of the person already with a job. The latter could be monitored for exposures and early effects of, for example, toxic substances on the genes. There are methods of detecting inherited predisposition to cardiovascular diseases as well as to adverse effects from

703

otherwise well-tolerated exposures related to the job. Clearly, with widespread use of genetic testing in the workplace there is the obvious danger of discrimination and stigmatization of individuals or groups. It may be tempting for employers to use tests to select only workers who will be able to work in the present working conditions, instead of improving the working conditions. The result could be that large groups of people would be barred from the job market. The discussion of the validity and predictive value of the methods used in genetic testing in the workplace including the ethical and societal issues raised by these methods has continued with many contributions. For instance, MacDonald and Williams-Jones 2002 discuss arguments for genetic testing the workplace, the objections to such testing, and propose pragmatic criteria, which – they argue – if met, “would make it permissible for employers to offer but not to require workplace genetic testing.” Particular attention has been focused on the risks for genetic discrimination (Krumm, 2002). This has been the central issue in the debate. Holtzman discusses the opinion by the European Group on Ethics on genetic testing in the workplace, in particular the implications of false positives and false negatives. Issues of employment in relation to genetic testing and Huntington’s disease (HD) have also been discussed against the background of a widely publicized case in Germany where a woman was refused employment as a teacher because of a family history of HD (Harper et al., 2004).

Forensic Testing A comparatively new use of genetic testing is to examine a possible genetic linkage between, for example, alleged fathers and their children, or between suspects and evidence discovered in criminal investigations, like hair, blood, sperm, saliva, or skin. The idea is to use genetic methods of analysis to clear the innocent and identify the guilty. However, concern has been expressed that mistakes can be made. Critics argue that it is necessary to improve the quality control of the test laboratories. Another problem is the confidentiality of the DNA profiles obtained from criminal investigations and stored in national police databanks. For how long time will they be stored? In some countries there are explicit limits to how long time they can be kept. Moreover, who will have access to them while they are stored, and for what purpose? In some countries, for instance Sweden, apparently no complete genetic analysis is carried out, and the samples are not saved. The information collected in criminal contexts is limited to what is required for a profile that is unique enough (with the exception for monozygotic twins and very close relatives). The intention is to minimize the possibility to extract general genetic information from the forensic data bases.

Concluding Remarks Since genomic technologies are able to detect genetic variations in patients with high accuracy and at reduced cost, these technologies may change the practice of medicine in the future. But genome-wide data raise many challenges concerning how they are to be interpreted and handled.

704

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

Genetic testing and screening should be done for ‘health purposes.’ This is sometimes stated as a necessary condition for genetic testing (Council of Europe, 1996, 2008). Health purposes could include diagnostic and therapeutic purposes as well as medical research and health care planning. Moreover, ‘health’ can be defined in several ways. It is important to state more precisely what this means. Careful counseling remains crucial, as already mentioned. The uncertainties and gaps in our knowledge referred to earlier have important implications for the information provided and the choices actually made. This applies both to monogenic and multifactorial inherited conditions. One of the present concerns is that do-it-yourself test kits for genetic disorders may be bought via the Internet or over the counter without any professional counseling to explain what the findings mean, how certain the test is, etc. There is an urgent need to find ways of regulating the economic interest of commercial biotechnological companies in order to minimize the harm of premature use and overuse of genetic testing. A matter of controversy is the extent to which attempts to individualize risks by pharmacogenomics (personalized medicine) will save money – and if so, how much – for the health care system. This depends on how the costs are estimated. Which costs, and whose costs, are included, and how are they estimated? Clearly it will have far-reaching effects on the education of medical doctors and the training of general practitioners – costs, which are not easy to estimate. Moreover, and perhaps more important, it will also have effects on the health care system, health care insurance, and priority setting in health care (Sahlin and Hermerén, 2011). Genetics has a somewhat dark history linked to eugenics. Eugenics can be organized by a state or a political party in power. But eugenic purposes can be also achieved by testing or screening methods in combination with social pressure to abort – and be facilitated by new technologies. Fear has sometimes been expressed that advances in molecular biology might speed up in vitro eugenics (Sparrow, 2013). Others (Da Fonseca, 2013) have argued that this is far away, due to the practical limitations to the technique of creating human gametes from stem cells.

See also: Eugenics as a Basis of Population Policy; Eugenics as an International Movement; Genetic Counseling: Historical, Ethical, and Practical Aspects; Genetic Screening for Disease.

Bibliography Allyse, M.A., Sayres, L.C., Havard, M., King, J.S., Greely, H.T., Hudgins, L., Taylor, J., Norton, M.E., Cho, M.K., Magnus, D., Ormond, K.E., July 2013. Best ethical practices for clinicians and laboratories in the provision of noninvasive prenatal testing. Prenatal Diagnosis 33 (7), 656–661. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/pd.4144. Buchanan, A., Brock, W., Daniels, N., Wikler, D., 2000. From Chance to Choice. Genetics and Justice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York. Bunnik, E.M., Janssens, A.C., Schermer, M.H., June 2013a. A tiered-layered-staged model for informed consent in personal genome testing. European Journal of Human Genetics 21 (6), 596–601. Bunnik, E.M., de Jong, A., Nijsingh, N., de Wert, G.M., July 2013b. The new genetics and informed consent: differentiating choice to preserve autonomy. Bioethics 27 (6), 348–355.

Canadian Human Rights Commission. Privacy Commissioner, 1992. Genetic Testing and Privacy. Privacy Commissioner of Canada, Ottawa, ON. Chadwick, R., 1998. The Ethics of Genetic Screening. Kluwer, Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Chadwick, R., Levitt, M., Shickle, D., 1997. The Right to Know and the Right Not to Know. Avebury, Aldershot, UK. Chadwick, R., ten Have, H., Husted, J., Levitt, M., McGleenan, D., Shickle, D., Wiesing, U., 1998. Genetic testing and ethics: European perspectives. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23, 255–273. Clarke, A. (Ed.), 1994. Genetic Counselling. Practice and Principles. Routledge, London. Clarke, A., Flinter, F., 1996. The genetic testing of children: a clinical perspective. In: Marteau, T.M., Richards, M.P. (Eds.), The Troubled Helix: Social and Psychological Implications of the New Human Genetics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 164–167. Council of Europe, 1996. Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine. Council of Europe, Strasbourg, France. Council of Europe, 2008. Additional Protocol to the Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine, Concerning Genetic Testing for Health Purposes. CETS, Strasbourg. No. 203. Dandara, C., Greenberg, J., Lambie, L., Lombard, Z., Naicker, T., Ramesar, R., Ramsay, M., Roberts, L., Theron, M., Venter, P., Bardien-Kruger, S., 4 July 2013. Direct-to-consumer genetic testing: to test or not to test, that is the question. South African Journal of Medicine 103 (8), 510–512. Danish Council of Ethics, 1993. Ethics and the Mapping of the Human Genome. Danish Council of Ethics, Copenhagen, Denmark. Davis, D.S., Spring 2013. Opportunistic testing: the death of informed consent? Health Matrix Clevel 23 (1), 35–54. Friedman Ross, L., 24/31 July 2013. Mandatory extended searches in all genome sequencing. “Incidental findings,” patient autonomy, and shared decision making. Journal of American Medical Association 310 (4), 367. da Fonseca, F.G., Ribeiro, D.M., Carvalho, N.P., Stancioli, B., 13 August 2013. Human in vitro eugenics: close, yet far away. Journal of Medical Ethics. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1136/medethics-2013-101674. Green, R.C., Lupski, J.R., Biesecker, L.G., 24/31 July 2013. Reporting genomic sequencing results to ordering clinicians. Incidental, but not exceptional. Journal of American Medical Association 310 (4), 365. Haker, H., 2008. Etische Dimensionen in der pränatalen Diagnostik. In: Hürlimann, D.C., Baumann-Hölzle, R., Müller, H. (Eds.), Der Beratungsprozess in der Pränatalen Diagnostik. Peter Lang, Bern, pp. 43–68. Harper, J.C., Harton, G., 2010. The use of arrays in preimplantation genetic diagnosis and screening. Fertility and Sterility 94 (4), 1173–1177. Harper, P.S., Clarke, A.J., 1997. Genetics, Society and Clinical Practice. Bios, Oxford, UK. Harper, P.S., Gevers, S., de Wert, G., Creighton, S., Bombard, S., Hayden, M.R., April 2004. Genetic Testing and Huntington’s disease: issues of employment. Lancet Neurology 3, 249–252. Hens, K., Dondorp, W., de Wert, G., 2013. Embryos without secrets. An expert panel study on comprehensive embryo testing and the responsibility of the clinician. European of Journal Medical Genetics 56, 67–71. Hepburn, E., 1996. Genetic testing and early diagnosis and intervention: boon or burden? Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (2), 105–110. Hermerén, G., 1999. Neonatal screening: ethical aspects. Acta Paediatrica (Suppl. 432), 99–103. Hermerén, G., 2000. The right to know and the right not to know. In: Who Owns Our Genes? Danish Council of Ethics, Copenhagen, Denmark, pp. 135–157. Hermerén, G., November 2012. The principle of proportionality revisited: interpretations and applications. Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy 15 (4), 373–382. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11019-011-9360x. Hogarth, S., Javitt, G., Melzer, D., 2008. The current landscape for direct-to-consumer genetic testing: legal, ethical, and policy issues. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 9, 161–182. Institute of Medicine, 1994. In: Andrew, L.B. (Ed.), Assessing Genetic Risks: Implications for Health and Social Policy. National Academy Press, Washington, DC. Jarvholm, B., Nordstrom, G., Hogstedt, B., Levin, J.O., Wahlstrom, J., Ostman, C., Bergendahl, C., 1999. Exposure to polycyclic aromatic hydrocarbons and genotoxic effects on nonsmoking Swedish road pavement workers. Scandinavian Journal of Work Environment & Health 25 (2), 131–136. de Jong, A., Dondorp, W.J., Timmermans, D.R., van Lith, J.M., de Wert, G.M., October 2011. Rapid aneuploidy detection or karyotyping? Ethical reflection. European Journal of Human Genetics 19 (10), 1020–1025.

Risk Screening, Testing, and Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects

Krumm, J., 2002. Genetic discrimination. Why Congress must ban genetic testing in the workplace. Journal of Legal Medicine 23, 491–521. Ma, Y., Gong, H., Wen, Y., June 2013. Nucleic acid-based non-invasive prenatal diagnosis of genetic skin diseases: are we ready? Experimental Dermatology 22 (6), 392–395. http://dx.doi.org/10.111/exd.12156. MacDonald, C., Williams-Jones, B., February 2002. Ethics and genetics: susceptibility testing in the workplace. Journal of Business Ethics 35 (3), 235–241. McGuire, A.L., Joffe, S., Koenig, B.A., Biesecker, B.B., McCullough, L.B., BlumenthalBarby, J.S., Caulfield, T., Terry, S.F., Green, R.C., May 31, 2013. Pointcounterpoint. Ethics and genomic incidental findings. Science 340 (6136), 1047–1048. Manson, N.C., O’Neill, O., 2007. Re-thinking Informed Consent in Bioethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Murray, T.H., 1983. Warning: screening workers for genetic risk. Hastings Center Report 13 (1), 5–8. Murray, T.H., Rothstein, M.A., Murray, R.F. (Eds.), 1996. The Human Genome Project and the Future of Health Care. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN. National Institutes of Health (National Human Genome Research Institute), 1997. Promoting Safe and Effective Genetic Testing in the United States: Principles and Recommendations. The report is available on the Internet at: http://www.nhgri.nih. gov/ELSI/TFGT_final. Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 1993. Genetic Screening: Ethical Issues. Nuffield, London. Patrinos, G.P., Baker, D.J., Al-Mulla, F., Vasiliou, V., Cooper, D.N., 2013. Genetic tests obtainable through pharmacies: the good, the bad, and the ugly. Human Genomics 8 (7), 17. http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1479-7364-7-17. Ravelingien, A., Pennings, G., 2013. The right to know your genetic parents: from open-identity gamete donation to routine paternity testing. American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5), 33–41. Rose, N.C., Dolan, S.M., October 2012. Newborn screening and the obstetrician. Obstetrics & Gynecology 120 (4), 908–917. Rhodes, R., 1998. Genetic links, family ties, and social bonds: rights and responsibilities in the face of genetic knowledge. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23 (1), 10–30. Sahlin, N.-E., Persson, J., 1994. Epistemic risk: the significance of knowing what one does not know. In: Brehmer, B., Sahlin, N.-E. (Eds.), Future Risks and Risk Management. Kluwer, Dordrecht, The Netherlands, pp. 37–62. Sahlin, N., Hermerén, G., 2011. Personalised, predictive and preventive medicine: a decision-theoretic perspective. Journal of Risk Research. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1080/13669877.2011.634524. Sandberg, P., 1996. Genetic Information and Life Insurance: A Proposal for an Ethical European Policy. Norwegian University of Science and Technology, Department of Biotechnology, Trondheim, Norway.

705

Schmitz, D., 2013. A new era in prenatal testing: are we prepared? Medical Healthcare and Philosophy 16, 357–364. Shenfield, F., 1997. Current ethical dilemmas in assisted reproduction. International Journal of Andrology 20 (Suppl. 3), 74–78. Shenfield, F., Sureau, C., 1997a. Ethics of embryo research. In: Shenfield, F., Sureau, C. (Eds.), Ethical Dilemmas in Assisted Reproduction. Parthenon, New York, pp. 15–21. Shenfield, F., Sureau, C. (Eds.), 1997b. Ethical Dilemmas in Assisted Reproduction. Parthenon, New York. Sparrow, R., 2013. In vitro eugenics. Journal of Medical Ethics. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1136/medethics-2012-101200. Published online First 4 April 2013. Surralles, J., Autio, K., Nylund, L., Jarventus, H., Norppa, H., Veidebaum, T., Sorsa, M., Peltonen, K., 1997. Molecular cytogenetic analysis of buccal cells and lymphocytes from benzene-exposed workers. Carcinogenesis 18 (4), 817–823. Takala, T., Hayry, M., 2000. Genetic ignorance, moral obligations and social duties. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (1), 107–113. Discussion 114–20. Tamir, S., March 2013. “Obligated aliens”: recognizing sperm donor’s ethical obligation to disclose genetic information. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23 (1), 19–52. UNESCO, 1997. Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights. UNESCO, Paris. Van Damme, K., Casteleyn, L., Heseltine, E., Huici, A., Sorsa, M., van Larebeke, N., Vineis, P., 1995. Individual susceptibility and prevention of occupational diseases: scientific and ethical issues. Journal of Occupational and Environmental Medicine 37 (1), 91–99. Van Damme, K., Vineis, P., Sorsa, M., Casteleyn, L., 1997. Ethical issues in genetic screening and genetic monitoring of employees. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 837, 554–565. Van Damme, K., Casteleyn, L., 1998. Ethical, social and scientific problems related to the application of genetic screening and genetic monitoring for workers in the context of a European approach to health and safety at work. La Medicina del Lavoro 89 (Suppl. 1). Wahlstrom, J., 1989. Inherited mental disorders. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica 80 (2), 111–117. Wertz, D., Fletcher, J., 1989. Ethics and Human Genetics: A Cross- Cultural Perspective. Springer, Berlin. Wright, C., 2009. Cell-free Fetal Nucleic Acids for Non-invasive Prenatal Diagnosis. Report of the UK expert working group. PHG Foundation. Zimmern, P., 1999. Genetic testing: a conceptual exploration. Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (2), 151–156.